Honestly, I didn't mean for that to be a pun. Liked it so much, I kept it.
Job and Ecclesiastes
The Iliad
The Odyssey
The Agamemnon
The Libation Bearers
The Eumenides
Prometheus Bound
Ajax
Antigone
The Histories of Herodotus
Common Sense
The Spirit of Laws
Second Treatise of Civil Government
The Anti-Capitalist Mentality
The Joke
Speed-The-Plow
Radical Chic
Mau-Mauing The Flak-Catchers
The Kandy-Kolored Tangerine-Flake Streamline Baby
The Dark Knight Returns
Batman: Year One
The Killing Joke
"We tend to scoff at the beliefs of the ancients. But we can't scoff at them personally, to their faces, and this is what annoys me." - Jack Handey
Saturday, November 12, 2011
Friday, August 26, 2011
The Killing Joke (Alan Moore)
I read this out of an Alan Moore collection from the library. And I read a few of his Superman stories from that collection before this one. It turns out that, for the most part, comic books are stupid.
This one wasn't, though. Even if I didn't get the end.
The overall idea is an interesting one: how close are we each from giving up on our moral compass and devotion to the social ethic? If we undergo an experience traumatic enough (caveat: it's more interesting when the Joker doesn't have a backstory. But within this book, it's not clear if the backstory is true, anyway) how will we react in an attempt to process what has happened?
Batman himself is right on that knife's edge. His traumatic loss of his parents has driven him to near lunacy. The only difference is he holds himself to a self-imposed moral code, but it's not at all clear that he does this out of any kind of rationality, or if his own irrational response just happened to take the form that it did. The Joker fell on one side of the line, Batman fell on the other, but the Joker is essentially right about the irrationality and amorality of the universe.
Commissioner Gordon, though, emerges as the moral rock at the center of Batman's world. Exposed to the same kind of trauma (worse, probably), he holds to the same moral principles he has always held-- and is not being irrational when he does so. He has always understood why Batman does what he does; he will not allow himself to fall into a similar gray zone of justice.
The Joker's adoption of the carnival freaks as his minions make an interesting symbolic point. There really is an unexplainable unfairness in the universe, that allows innocent individuals to be born into such handicaps. It is a condition that cries out for a justification. And, if none is forthcoming, it is easy to conclude that there is no justice to be bound to in the first place.
The Dark Knight did a good job of exploring these influences on and implications of the Joker's actions, but this story nails down the themes in a very succinct and concrete way.
But the end of the book was lousy.
This one wasn't, though. Even if I didn't get the end.
The overall idea is an interesting one: how close are we each from giving up on our moral compass and devotion to the social ethic? If we undergo an experience traumatic enough (caveat: it's more interesting when the Joker doesn't have a backstory. But within this book, it's not clear if the backstory is true, anyway) how will we react in an attempt to process what has happened?
Batman himself is right on that knife's edge. His traumatic loss of his parents has driven him to near lunacy. The only difference is he holds himself to a self-imposed moral code, but it's not at all clear that he does this out of any kind of rationality, or if his own irrational response just happened to take the form that it did. The Joker fell on one side of the line, Batman fell on the other, but the Joker is essentially right about the irrationality and amorality of the universe.
Commissioner Gordon, though, emerges as the moral rock at the center of Batman's world. Exposed to the same kind of trauma (worse, probably), he holds to the same moral principles he has always held-- and is not being irrational when he does so. He has always understood why Batman does what he does; he will not allow himself to fall into a similar gray zone of justice.
The Joker's adoption of the carnival freaks as his minions make an interesting symbolic point. There really is an unexplainable unfairness in the universe, that allows innocent individuals to be born into such handicaps. It is a condition that cries out for a justification. And, if none is forthcoming, it is easy to conclude that there is no justice to be bound to in the first place.
The Dark Knight did a good job of exploring these influences on and implications of the Joker's actions, but this story nails down the themes in a very succinct and concrete way.
But the end of the book was lousy.
The Joke (Milan Kundera)
This is a nearly random one-shot novel that was referenced in one of Mark Steyn's National Review columns. No association with anything else-- except, when I see well-read people refer to something, I feel like I should know what they're talking about.
For the first half of the book, I was viewing it as a terrifying illustration of the operation of a Communist state-- the point that Steyn was making. But the introduction warned against treating it as a political novel. The introduction was right. By the end, I viewed it much more as an exploration of different viewpoints of life in general, and the paradoxes of filtering reality through our own subjective consciousness.
It's also a good thing that I read the book in under 48 hours. The shifting-narrator structure wouldn't have made sense otherwise, and I never would have caught on to the reemergence of characters from their fleeting mentions in prior narrations. It felt like an episode of LOST at times. Very effective.
Bullet points:
For the first half of the book, I was viewing it as a terrifying illustration of the operation of a Communist state-- the point that Steyn was making. But the introduction warned against treating it as a political novel. The introduction was right. By the end, I viewed it much more as an exploration of different viewpoints of life in general, and the paradoxes of filtering reality through our own subjective consciousness.
It's also a good thing that I read the book in under 48 hours. The shifting-narrator structure wouldn't have made sense otherwise, and I never would have caught on to the reemergence of characters from their fleeting mentions in prior narrations. It felt like an episode of LOST at times. Very effective.
Bullet points:
- Much romantic life-- at least each individual side of an unrequited love-- is a struggle to impose a coherent narrative on what is objectively unconnected events and actions.
- In a related way, the political project of Communism is the imposition of control of control and coherence on what is necessarily (because it depends on the actions of independent agents) a series of isolated social interactions. In the same way the lover is seeking bliss, the Communist seeks to achieve social perfection.
- This involves the replacement of organic culture with a simulation instead-- a simulation designed toward the imagined utopia of the future. It is believed that the artificial imitation can do the job of culture just as well as the genuine article, as long as it is simply successfully inserted into the correct social position.
- This is most notable-- and off-putting-- when religious ceremonies are stamped out in favor of Party social rituals. The actions are drained of their content, leaving only a shell of an empty formalism.
- Perhaps the most drastic imposition is forced labor camps, designed to simulate acts of penance against a controlling moral authority.
- I was greatly impressed by the plot twists sprinkled throughout the story-- especially the revelation that Ludvik was pursuing Helena purely as revenge against his enemy Zemanek. Hidden very well until the last name was suddenly mentioned. It's also possible that Ludvik was originally marked for special attention by the Party at school because of his defense of Kostka's religiosity. The only one that didn't work for me organically in the story was Lucie's relationship with Kostka after Ludvik's relationship with her ended It was simply too coincidental that those two characters' paths would cross separately from their prior relationships with Ludvik.
- I would have enjoyed a chapter narrated by Zemanek, covering his perspective of Ludvik's trial, and the gradual lessening of his intense devotion to Party.
- I enjoyed the explanation that the next generation at the school was entirely uninterested in the battles fought by the prior classes and their devotion to the Party. Another instance of an attempt to impose an overarching logic onto a reality that simply refuses to support our aims. This was also illustrated well by Jaroslav's son blowing off the folk ceremony.
- Ludvik's final identification of the "mistakes" that controlled his life was also interesting. What we call "errors" can only be so against a backdrop of correct actions-- defined in reference to the logic we're trying to impose or extract from the world. But from the perspective of History, all events are simply events. The "errors" are the history-- and there is nothing else.
- And this is the theme of the book: that the world does not react to our grand designs for it.
Yes, suddenly I saw it clearly: most people deceive themselves with a pair of faiths: they believe in eternal memory (of people, things, deeds, nations) and in redressibility (of deeds, mistakes, sins, wrongs). Both are false faiths. In reality the opposite is true: everything will be forgotten and nothing will be redressed. The task of obtaining redress (by vengeance or by forgiveness) will be taken over by forgetting. No one will redress the wrongs that have been done, but all wrongs will be forgotten.
Sunday, July 31, 2011
Batman: Year One (Frank Miller)
Color me unimpressed. Batman needs villains, and he didn't have any here. The whole thing felt like it never got off the ground. Yeah, yeah... Batman needs to be created, and he doesn't quite know what he's doing at first. But ultimately, nothing is at stake except for some (mostly) petty crime. I needed a bigger conflict to hold my attention.
I suppose this was a good exploration of the psychology of Lt. Gordon. If that hadn't been delved into before, it was very nicely done. And it nicely wraps together a whole slew of characters that I recognize from other references-- Harvey Dent, Carmine Falcone, Catwoman, and Det. Flass among them.
But Batman needs villains.
Though the overall theme made for one helluva movie.
I suppose this was a good exploration of the psychology of Lt. Gordon. If that hadn't been delved into before, it was very nicely done. And it nicely wraps together a whole slew of characters that I recognize from other references-- Harvey Dent, Carmine Falcone, Catwoman, and Det. Flass among them.
But Batman needs villains.
Though the overall theme made for one helluva movie.
Thursday, July 28, 2011
The Anti-Capitalistic Mentality (Ludwig von Mises)
I felt like a needed a little background before getting into my Hayek books, and according to Russ Roberts, Mises was a big influence. I don't think I'm up for academic tracts, though, so this was a relatively short sample (picked basically at random out of what was available in the library) of what I can expect from popular economics.
At first, I didn't appreciate Mises' hectoring tone, scolding the unsuccessful for their jealousy of the rich. I mean, even if he's right, he doesn't have to say it like that. But I realized throughout the book that Mises felt that tone was necessary to wake up his audience to the damage that could be done by the enemies of capitalism. If he was writing this in the 70's, he was writing in a crisis moment. There was no time for gladhanding the naysayers. It was buck up the capitalists, or perish.
Bullet points I picked up on throughout the book:
At first, I didn't appreciate Mises' hectoring tone, scolding the unsuccessful for their jealousy of the rich. I mean, even if he's right, he doesn't have to say it like that. But I realized throughout the book that Mises felt that tone was necessary to wake up his audience to the damage that could be done by the enemies of capitalism. If he was writing this in the 70's, he was writing in a crisis moment. There was no time for gladhanding the naysayers. It was buck up the capitalists, or perish.
Bullet points I picked up on throughout the book:
- The consumer is ultimate sovereign. If the public won't buy your product, your business will fail. Economic growth (not to say success or moral goodness) only comes from serving the fulfilling the public's desire.
- The players that produce real progress are the saver who provides capital, the entrepreneur who attempts to create a product to sell to the masses, and the technologist who invents means of greater efficiency. All other participants are bit players, essentially interchangeable parts. Resentment at recognizing this leads to the anti-capitalist mentality, even as the successes of the progress-makers ("progressive classes") improve the lives of all (as witnessed by their eager consumption of those goods).
- SAVING is the primary act. Growth can't come intially from spending, or from boosting demand as the first step in the chain (although all these actions are cyclically related to each other). But saving is primary-- it gives the essential "slack" (my word) necessary to attempt something new, the success of which is the basis for real economic growth.
- Capitalism is accused of debasing the culture-- by flooding the market with trash literature, it crowds out real art and real profundity. Poppycock. Goodness and badness in art is independent of commercial success. Commercial participation in the arts in no way precludes the possibility of great art. Capitalistic participation merely indicates a desire of the public that was previously unmet-- THEY determine what sells. And in prior days, profound art was unavailable for public consumption anyway, no less so than today. Existence in a capitalistic society in no way precludes the pursuit of great art, if that is what the artist wants from his life.
- Capitalism and communism-- identical to socialism-- are diametrically opposed. There is no middle ground, no waystation, in interventionism-- it is only a step toward communism. The founders of communism certainly saw it that way.
- Anti-capitalist literature depends almost fully on a misrepresentation of the conditions of people-- both the poor it tries to inspire to rise up, and of the businessmen it accuses of unadulterated treachery. It is silly not to recognize this as it is happening.
- Mises goes into a severe criticism of the concept of natural rights-- though it's not clear if he would disagree with Locke's concept of natural rights or the Founders' concept. His main point seems to be only that there is no natural right to an even share in the goods or the wealth within the society-- for where did that wealth arise from to begin with? Only through the tortured application of reason and ingenuity on the part of human actors. Nature provides nothing. This is an argument against the concept of a natural right to freedom from material want as put forward by the early 20th century Progressives.
- Increased efficiency (either through improved technology or entrepreneurial insight) raises the marginal value of the labor employed in the process (possibly because it gets by with a lower total amount of it?). That increase in value corresponds to rising wages within that industry. In turn, this raises the wages of labor throughout society, for employers must pay more to prevent employees from leaving to enter the improved industry. This is all possible system-wide essentially because of the gradual accumulation of capital-- that is, through the saving made possible by the increased efficiency. And saving is sustainable only because useful production outpaces consumption-- and that happens through the application of human ingenuity.
- Me : Is this the ultimate argument against centrally planned economy? A government CANNOT save; it will always insist on distributing for consumption ALL of its production. Even a longer-term plan on the part of the government will have the eventual future consumption locked into law, undeferrable. Capitalism, and the progress it generates, requires private property rights and private control of the means of production, because only a private actor can accumulate capital by saving-- by foregoing consumption-- in the first place. Only a private actor can plan ahead and recognize an opportunity for future benefit through delayed gratification.
- The ultimate source of this idea is the concept of individual liberty first proposed by the Greeks (flawed as their concept was). The modern capitalist age drew explicitly on the cultural tradition first laid down by the Greeks. The actions of this century's perverted liberals-- adopting a sort of "super-liberalism" (Mises' word) that sought the emancipation of all people from the vicissitudes of Nature and of inequality (not recognizing how that inequality arose)-- first sought to overturn the primacy of the ancient cultural tradition from the public mind. This is a complete reversal of real liberty.
- p. 101: "Freedom under capitalism means: not to depend more on other people's discretion than these others depend on one's own." We ourselves make the rich rich by buying their products. In turn we gain the benefits of the improvements they try to sell. Everyone is reliant upon everyone else-- but everyone has skin and a say in the game as well. What more do we want?
- The hectoring of the intellectual class, through their freedom to express their views, is the price we pay to secure the freedom required for the capitalists to do their thing without government interference. What it requires in turn is vigilance, and active argument in support of our own point of view.
Saturday, July 16, 2011
The Kandy-Kolored Tangerine-Flake Streamline Baby (Tom Wolfe)
Las Vegas... demolition derby... self-promoting DJs... Jersey teeny-boppers... Phil Spector... custom cars... Cassius Clay... NASCAR country... Cary Grant... seedy gossip tabloids... the IT girl... urban archetypes... public trendsetters... conservative aesthetic crusaders... the Art Scene... men's fashion... nanny culture... the generation gap... Sunday leisure... rich divorcées...women's prison... doormen... status in the city.
America rocks.*
What I got out of this book is utter delight in and celebration of the strands of American culture. I could also see Tom Wolfe dipping his toe into the stream-of-consciousness style. Most importantly, he treats all of his subjects with glowing, genuine respect. Only when he's writing about the ultra-rich does a wink sneak in to acknowledge the utter ridiculousness of their behavior. (As opposed to his portrayal of the hippies in The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test, in which he never stopped winking.)
*(Except for Phil Spector. On the other hand, anyone who could write this:
can't be all bad.)
America rocks.*
What I got out of this book is utter delight in and celebration of the strands of American culture. I could also see Tom Wolfe dipping his toe into the stream-of-consciousness style. Most importantly, he treats all of his subjects with glowing, genuine respect. Only when he's writing about the ultra-rich does a wink sneak in to acknowledge the utter ridiculousness of their behavior. (As opposed to his portrayal of the hippies in The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test, in which he never stopped winking.)
*(Except for Phil Spector. On the other hand, anyone who could write this:
can't be all bad.)
Friday, July 08, 2011
The Dark Knight Returns (Frank Miller)
This is the first graphic novel I've ever read. And it's the first comic book I've read since Dennis the Menace Learns the Our Father (the Protestant version, anyway). The plan is to get a feel for the format with a few Batman titles before diving into Watchmen. In any case, I'm impressed.
What surprised me the most was the inferences I had to draw as the reader from very few details in each panel. And yet, the the implications were all fully there on the page.
Another aspect that I enjoyed: the critical commentary about many elements of modern society that I privately rail against as well. Unserious media, relativistic reluctance to name evil as evil, hippie parents, therapeutic solutions to spiritual problems... it's all there.
I love Batman making fun of Superman. Come on, you pansy.
So apparently it's well-established that Frank Miller wrote Batman as an explicitly Catholic character. To that end, I loved the shout-out to Catholicism's devotion to absolute truth in the face of ever-changing worldly fashions:
What surprised me the most was the inferences I had to draw as the reader from very few details in each panel. And yet, the the implications were all fully there on the page.
Another aspect that I enjoyed: the critical commentary about many elements of modern society that I privately rail against as well. Unserious media, relativistic reluctance to name evil as evil, hippie parents, therapeutic solutions to spiritual problems... it's all there.
I love Batman making fun of Superman. Come on, you pansy.
So apparently it's well-established that Frank Miller wrote Batman as an explicitly Catholic character. To that end, I loved the shout-out to Catholicism's devotion to absolute truth in the face of ever-changing worldly fashions:
The Pope today declared that the Church's stand on contraception will not change, despite yesterday's firebombing of St. Peter's Square.That's right.
Thursday, June 30, 2011
Speed-The-Plow (David Mamet)
What I love about Mamet's plays is the way the context of the conversation changes in a instant, but it's immediately evident what the new context is.
Excuse me.
Character 1: The thing about Mamet is, is the context turns on a fucken' dime...
Character 2: On a fucken' dime.
Character 1: Right, on a fucken' dime, but it's clear as day what everybody's state of mind is.
Character 2: Bullshit.
Anyway, you've got two producers who seem to be pleased with their work-- they're making a good deal on a movie project!
Boom. Nope, they're only excited about the money.
Boom. Nope, what they really want is to shove the money in the faces (or up the asses) of everyone who stood in their way.
Karen walks in, and the guys start showing off by being more vulgar than before. What they actually want is sex-- but they're mostly insecure about it. Enchanting.
At Gould's place, Karen makes her pitch (though she is unable to make the one-sentence pitch a movie deal requires.) It doesn't work.
Boom. She switches to seduction. Gould doesn't notice.
In the office, Fox is livid. (Actually, he goes through Denial, Anger, and Bargaining in about a page and a half). He's actaully been jealous of Gould his whole career, but was willing to hide it as long as he could be dragged upward with him.
Ultimately, the movies are a business where everybody claims to be producing art, while in actuality it's entirely built on power plays. "It's about people." Still a half-truth.
Excuse me.
Character 1: The thing about Mamet is, is the context turns on a fucken' dime...
Character 2: On a fucken' dime.
Character 1: Right, on a fucken' dime, but it's clear as day what everybody's state of mind is.
Character 2: Bullshit.
Anyway, you've got two producers who seem to be pleased with their work-- they're making a good deal on a movie project!
Boom. Nope, they're only excited about the money.
Boom. Nope, what they really want is to shove the money in the faces (or up the asses) of everyone who stood in their way.
Karen walks in, and the guys start showing off by being more vulgar than before. What they actually want is sex-- but they're mostly insecure about it. Enchanting.
At Gould's place, Karen makes her pitch (though she is unable to make the one-sentence pitch a movie deal requires.) It doesn't work.
Boom. She switches to seduction. Gould doesn't notice.
In the office, Fox is livid. (Actually, he goes through Denial, Anger, and Bargaining in about a page and a half). He's actaully been jealous of Gould his whole career, but was willing to hide it as long as he could be dragged upward with him.
Ultimately, the movies are a business where everybody claims to be producing art, while in actuality it's entirely built on power plays. "It's about people." Still a half-truth.
Sunday, June 12, 2011
Mau-Mauing The Flak Catchers (Tom Wolfe)
It's all an illusion. Government programs, class struggles, status-climbing, identity politics, community organizing-- all of it.
Those who design top-down programs and solutions think that they will make a dent in the problem. What's the problem? Well... clearly there is a problem, and clearly we have in mind that we will do something about it, and in the end, clearly that will indeed come to pass. Because how could it not?
Every participant uses the system in place for ends other than what the system was put in place for. Community leaders hand out favors to friends. Government bureaucrats check boxes on a checklist, their assignments fulfilled. Status-seekers see an opening and make a move for themselves. Children are conscripted for image management purposes. Teachers create lessons to raise awareness-- the most important thing that can be done for a learner. Writers claim to have discovered The Answer, while cultural guideposts pick winners nearly at random. Money is flung around because money is the only medium known to produce results-- the mere use of it must be part of the solution!
Is there an alternative? Well... an alternative to what? If you never define the problem you can insist that only your actions can possibly solve it. Who can propose a better way? How could they possibly show their way to be better?
------------------------
I guess I hinted at this same problem in the last post, but here it is again. Trying to wrap my head around macroscopic sociological problems-- or even macroscopic descriptions of society-- drives me crazy. Wolfe's style is very helpful in explaining why this might be so-- because the most likely case is that it doesn't make any sense. The best way to realize that is to see whaat we actually see in our everyday experience of the world and the large society we live in-- only disjointed facts and impressions, that whirl around while the rational part of our brains try to tell some kind of narrative that makes sense. It could very well be that we're not wired to make sense of that level of abstraction.
---------------------------
On another note, I have noticed that my posts tend to be written in the voice of the author I just read-- or at least a facsimile of that voice. This is not a new phenomenon. Thinking back to high school and my first years of college, I often fell asleep trying to read whatever was in front of me (that I had put off until I was too tired to actually get through it-- some things never change). Fiction, non-fiction, magazines, whatever. And I always had dreams narrated in the style of whomever I had been reading. I can distinctly remember this happening with Tom Clancy more than anything else. Upon waking, I'd notice that whatever the narrator had been saying was utter, utter nonsense, and then the content of that narration would fade completely. But the tone remained (even if I was unable to reproduce it while I was awake).
Anyway, it's happening again, especially in the entries for Chesterton and Wolfe. I'm glad that it is. In Chesterton's case, his tone is so lofty I want to capture it as my own. In Wolfe's case, it would be impossible to take careful sequential notes of what he writes-- and I wouldn't want to anyway. As I mentioned above, the free-wheeling style is the only way to make sense of his subject matter in the first place.
Those who design top-down programs and solutions think that they will make a dent in the problem. What's the problem? Well... clearly there is a problem, and clearly we have in mind that we will do something about it, and in the end, clearly that will indeed come to pass. Because how could it not?
Every participant uses the system in place for ends other than what the system was put in place for. Community leaders hand out favors to friends. Government bureaucrats check boxes on a checklist, their assignments fulfilled. Status-seekers see an opening and make a move for themselves. Children are conscripted for image management purposes. Teachers create lessons to raise awareness-- the most important thing that can be done for a learner. Writers claim to have discovered The Answer, while cultural guideposts pick winners nearly at random. Money is flung around because money is the only medium known to produce results-- the mere use of it must be part of the solution!
Is there an alternative? Well... an alternative to what? If you never define the problem you can insist that only your actions can possibly solve it. Who can propose a better way? How could they possibly show their way to be better?
------------------------
I guess I hinted at this same problem in the last post, but here it is again. Trying to wrap my head around macroscopic sociological problems-- or even macroscopic descriptions of society-- drives me crazy. Wolfe's style is very helpful in explaining why this might be so-- because the most likely case is that it doesn't make any sense. The best way to realize that is to see whaat we actually see in our everyday experience of the world and the large society we live in-- only disjointed facts and impressions, that whirl around while the rational part of our brains try to tell some kind of narrative that makes sense. It could very well be that we're not wired to make sense of that level of abstraction.
---------------------------
On another note, I have noticed that my posts tend to be written in the voice of the author I just read-- or at least a facsimile of that voice. This is not a new phenomenon. Thinking back to high school and my first years of college, I often fell asleep trying to read whatever was in front of me (that I had put off until I was too tired to actually get through it-- some things never change). Fiction, non-fiction, magazines, whatever. And I always had dreams narrated in the style of whomever I had been reading. I can distinctly remember this happening with Tom Clancy more than anything else. Upon waking, I'd notice that whatever the narrator had been saying was utter, utter nonsense, and then the content of that narration would fade completely. But the tone remained (even if I was unable to reproduce it while I was awake).
Anyway, it's happening again, especially in the entries for Chesterton and Wolfe. I'm glad that it is. In Chesterton's case, his tone is so lofty I want to capture it as my own. In Wolfe's case, it would be impossible to take careful sequential notes of what he writes-- and I wouldn't want to anyway. As I mentioned above, the free-wheeling style is the only way to make sense of his subject matter in the first place.
Labels:
Mau-Mauing the Flak Catchers,
meta,
sidelights,
Tom Wolfe
Saturday, June 11, 2011
Radical Chic (Tom Wolfe)
Man, I love that stream-of-consciousness style. It really does paint the room, and even the subjective experience of the room. And I've found the less carefully you read-- the more you just let the words stream in-- the clearer the picture.
Maybe I just know a lot more than I did before, but it was surprising how familiar the names were in comparison to those in The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test. Leonard Bernstein, Barbara Walters, William F. Buckley. Cool stuff.
Biting commentary on the whole idea of high society. Intended that way? Isn't Tom Wolfe a member of high society?
The political tensions are clear enough. It's probable that social gulfs can't be bridged in one evening. What progress did they actually expect to make?
Loved the continued insistence at the end that it was a "meeting, not a party." Oh, but the white servants...
I was taken aback by the final turn of the tale. In the end, the movers and shakers lost control of their image, and of the story. A good lesson there: With status comes notoriety, but not necessarily a whole lot of power. Trend-setters can set the trends within those arenas that others look to them to set trends. But political trends come from elsewhere. Or were they simply trying to plant the next flag against an up-and-coming new wave of high society-- was it merely a social experiment? Simply a gamble-- within their own world-- that didn't pay off?
I'd like to see Buckley's essay about the meeting.
One theme that has bothered me more and more in general, and that struck me in particular in the essay (so I might as well bring it up now): I don't think I understand the psychology of identity politics. Meaning, I genuinely don't think of myself as represented by, or representative of, any class at all. That's easy enough to say as a white middle-class man, but it applies to those minority groups of which I am a part as well-- I never felt nor do I feel personally implicated in any criticism of the Catholic Church, for instance. In the realm of abstraction, I'll think through arguments implicating the abstract idea. And I'll take note of how other individuals within the group are treated as individuals. But I never feel like the abstract idea has much of an effect on me. In the end, I see myself as an individual who works and lives, and is treated in a certain way by the people I interact with, and take those interactions as significant only for myself-- because how could the other person actually be acting as if they are interacting with an abstraction? How could I?
So what am I doing wrong? Because given the way other people talk and write about the way they see and behave in the world, it often feels like I'm missing out on something big.
Maybe I just know a lot more than I did before, but it was surprising how familiar the names were in comparison to those in The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test. Leonard Bernstein, Barbara Walters, William F. Buckley. Cool stuff.
Biting commentary on the whole idea of high society. Intended that way? Isn't Tom Wolfe a member of high society?
The political tensions are clear enough. It's probable that social gulfs can't be bridged in one evening. What progress did they actually expect to make?
Loved the continued insistence at the end that it was a "meeting, not a party." Oh, but the white servants...
I was taken aback by the final turn of the tale. In the end, the movers and shakers lost control of their image, and of the story. A good lesson there: With status comes notoriety, but not necessarily a whole lot of power. Trend-setters can set the trends within those arenas that others look to them to set trends. But political trends come from elsewhere. Or were they simply trying to plant the next flag against an up-and-coming new wave of high society-- was it merely a social experiment? Simply a gamble-- within their own world-- that didn't pay off?
I'd like to see Buckley's essay about the meeting.
One theme that has bothered me more and more in general, and that struck me in particular in the essay (so I might as well bring it up now): I don't think I understand the psychology of identity politics. Meaning, I genuinely don't think of myself as represented by, or representative of, any class at all. That's easy enough to say as a white middle-class man, but it applies to those minority groups of which I am a part as well-- I never felt nor do I feel personally implicated in any criticism of the Catholic Church, for instance. In the realm of abstraction, I'll think through arguments implicating the abstract idea. And I'll take note of how other individuals within the group are treated as individuals. But I never feel like the abstract idea has much of an effect on me. In the end, I see myself as an individual who works and lives, and is treated in a certain way by the people I interact with, and take those interactions as significant only for myself-- because how could the other person actually be acting as if they are interacting with an abstraction? How could I?
So what am I doing wrong? Because given the way other people talk and write about the way they see and behave in the world, it often feels like I'm missing out on something big.
Sidelines (Ed.: Sidelights?)
It can get awfully boring limiting oneself to a set sequence of books. And it can get mighty annoying reading just enough to outline in a post, and no more. I'm getting a little sick of it at the moment. Can't I just read?
So, a new addition. Random insertions of non-classics, read quickly and immersively (well, more immersively). Library books, many of them will be. They'll get single entries, and I'll feel free to move on. Capice?
Sudden panic, however: do I call these sidelines, or sidelights? Apple's Dashboard dictionary says:
sideline - an activity done in addition to one's main job
sidelight - a piece of incidental information that helps to clarify or enliven a subject
They're both right! Ummm..... sidelights it is. (The whole damn blog is a sideline.)
So, a new addition. Random insertions of non-classics, read quickly and immersively (well, more immersively). Library books, many of them will be. They'll get single entries, and I'll feel free to move on. Capice?
Sudden panic, however: do I call these sidelines, or sidelights? Apple's Dashboard dictionary says:
sideline - an activity done in addition to one's main job
sidelight - a piece of incidental information that helps to clarify or enliven a subject
They're both right! Ummm..... sidelights it is. (The whole damn blog is a sideline.)
Tuesday, May 31, 2011
Antigone, 4
The prophet Tiresias enters to tell off Creon. He has seen only bad omens-- bad, bad omens. Creon blows him off, and accuses him of faking bad news for payment. Creon is losing all control. So Tiresias finally lays out all his crimes and sins in one fell swoop. 1) Sentencing a mere child to death. 2) Dishonored an honorable soldier's body. 3) Defied his own flesh and blood. 4) Fomented revolution among the people he is supposed to lead. Tiresias walks out in disgust.
Creon is finally shaken in fear. He will free Antigone if he can, and regrets defying the law of the gods. The Chorus beg to Bacchus to come and set things right.
After a time, a messenger arrives with news of Creon's despair. Haemon is dead by suicide. Eurydice (Creon's wife and Haemon's mother) enters distrught, and the messenger tells the story. He and Haemon went and performed the proper burial rites on Polyneices rotting body. Haemon then went to free Antigone, but found her having hanged herself. Creon also arrived, setting off Haemon's rage. He lunged at his father, then stabbed himself with his own sword, embracing Antigone in his death.
Eurydice leaves, and Creon enters with Haemon's body. He is broken. The same messenger enters again with more news: Eurydice has killed herself with her dagger. What is more, she cursed and blamed Creon for all the death's before committing the act. Creon has lost everything.
The Chorus's final lesson:
Very bloody ending, moreso than anything I've read so far. Inspiration to Shakespeare?
In the end, Creon did respect a higher authority-- the words of the prophet shook him to his core. He really did understand that his actions were subject to the law of the gods. But in his arrogance, he would not believe any of those who tried to warn him of that, distrusting their motives-- even disbelieving the prophet for a time, treating him as a huckster. A little paranoia mixed in with the megalomania, I think.
Another lesson: justice does indeed come in the end onto those who test it. From the very beginning of his rampage, Creon's fate was sealed. It was only a matter of time.
Creon is finally shaken in fear. He will free Antigone if he can, and regrets defying the law of the gods. The Chorus beg to Bacchus to come and set things right.
After a time, a messenger arrives with news of Creon's despair. Haemon is dead by suicide. Eurydice (Creon's wife and Haemon's mother) enters distrught, and the messenger tells the story. He and Haemon went and performed the proper burial rites on Polyneices rotting body. Haemon then went to free Antigone, but found her having hanged herself. Creon also arrived, setting off Haemon's rage. He lunged at his father, then stabbed himself with his own sword, embracing Antigone in his death.
Eurydice leaves, and Creon enters with Haemon's body. He is broken. The same messenger enters again with more news: Eurydice has killed herself with her dagger. What is more, she cursed and blamed Creon for all the death's before committing the act. Creon has lost everything.
The Chorus's final lesson:
Where wisdom is, there happiness will crown--------------------------
A piety that nothing will corrode.
But high and mighty words and ways
Are flogged to humbleness, till age,
Beaten to its knees, at last is wise.
Very bloody ending, moreso than anything I've read so far. Inspiration to Shakespeare?
In the end, Creon did respect a higher authority-- the words of the prophet shook him to his core. He really did understand that his actions were subject to the law of the gods. But in his arrogance, he would not believe any of those who tried to warn him of that, distrusting their motives-- even disbelieving the prophet for a time, treating him as a huckster. A little paranoia mixed in with the megalomania, I think.
Another lesson: justice does indeed come in the end onto those who test it. From the very beginning of his rampage, Creon's fate was sealed. It was only a matter of time.
Antigone, 3
Haemon enters, and states that he plans to speak as Creon's son. Creon is pleased, and tells his son he shouldn't marry such a disobedient girl. Also speaks at length on the right of a political leader to rule his people with an iron fist-- in that true justice lies. Haemon quietly rebukes him, saying that as his son he begs his father to do real justice for Antigone, and that the people in the streets of Thebes are uniformly against their leader. The words between them grow heated, and nearly hysterical on Creon's part. Haemon continues to plead for the justice of heaven be done, while Creon contends that the justice of power is justice. Haemon walks out. Creon describes the punishment that Antigone will receive: isolation in cave until she expires.
The Chorus lament the effects of love on familial relations.
Antigone is brought in once more to face Creon. She is resigned to her punishment, and sees it as the culmination of the curse upon her family. Creon enters to give the final sentence, and Antigone is defiant to his face once again. She also gives a final justification for her act: her love for her dead brother cannot be made up for toward any other. She maintains the justice of her actions, and only hopes that true justice will eventually be done to those who wrong her.
The Chorus lament again, and name Antigone as the continuation of a long line of Greek women who suffered in seclusion and isolation.
------------------------
More development of the political philosophy here. Creon does possess absolute power, but the people are free to resist and eventually to abandon their leader, and will do so if they do not see him aligning with their sense of a higher justice.
The Chorus lament the effects of love on familial relations.
Antigone is brought in once more to face Creon. She is resigned to her punishment, and sees it as the culmination of the curse upon her family. Creon enters to give the final sentence, and Antigone is defiant to his face once again. She also gives a final justification for her act: her love for her dead brother cannot be made up for toward any other. She maintains the justice of her actions, and only hopes that true justice will eventually be done to those who wrong her.
The Chorus lament again, and name Antigone as the continuation of a long line of Greek women who suffered in seclusion and isolation.
------------------------
More development of the political philosophy here. Creon does possess absolute power, but the people are free to resist and eventually to abandon their leader, and will do so if they do not see him aligning with their sense of a higher justice.
Monday, May 30, 2011
Antigone, 2
Chorus sings a song extolling the dominance of man over the world-- over the natural world, which he has subdued, and over the political world, which bends to his whims. But end on a word of warning against ambition overstepping its bounds.
Sentry reenters with Antigone in tow. He cheerfully and at great length tells how she was caught red-handed re-burying the body (after the guards had dusted it off the first time). Antigone stands up to Creon, denying nothing, and claiming that she was following a higher law-- a law the Creon has not the authority to nullify. Creon is angered even more. Biting back-and-forth between the two, neither giving an inch.
Ismene is brought in, to be punished as an accomplice, a role she gladly accepts now that her remaining family is doomed. Antigone ruefully denies her that title, for she wouldn't go along with her plan at the beginning. Ismene tries to save Antigone by pointing out she is betrothed to Creon's son Haemon-- just throwing another duty onto the pile. Taken aback, Creon sends them both to be locked up while he figures out what to do next.
The Chorus sings a song lamenting the terrible fate that continues to wend its way through the family of Oedipus. The gods are exceptionally cruel, and wicked in their play.
Haemon enters.
Sentry reenters with Antigone in tow. He cheerfully and at great length tells how she was caught red-handed re-burying the body (after the guards had dusted it off the first time). Antigone stands up to Creon, denying nothing, and claiming that she was following a higher law-- a law the Creon has not the authority to nullify. Creon is angered even more. Biting back-and-forth between the two, neither giving an inch.
Ismene is brought in, to be punished as an accomplice, a role she gladly accepts now that her remaining family is doomed. Antigone ruefully denies her that title, for she wouldn't go along with her plan at the beginning. Ismene tries to save Antigone by pointing out she is betrothed to Creon's son Haemon-- just throwing another duty onto the pile. Taken aback, Creon sends them both to be locked up while he figures out what to do next.
The Chorus sings a song lamenting the terrible fate that continues to wend its way through the family of Oedipus. The gods are exceptionally cruel, and wicked in their play.
Haemon enters.
Sunday, May 29, 2011
Antigone, 1
After Oedipus's death, a war rages for the control of Thebes. Oedipus's two sons, Polyneices and Eteocles, are killed on opposite sides of the battle. Oedipus's brother Creon, now the acting king, declares that Polyneices's body should receive no burial, he being on the rebellion side of the battle. Oedipus's daughter Antigone vows to give her brother a proper burial, just as Eteocles rightly received. She tries to talk her sister Ismene into aiding her in the burial, but Ismene is too fearful to do so-- and does not want to contribute to her family's sad history of ignominy. Disgusted, Antigone asks her instead to proclaim loudly what she intends to do-- she welcomes the punishment of death that Creon has threatened, as long as she is seen to do right by her family.
Thebes's soldiers (the Chorus) enter, bragging loudly over their victory. Creon enters and clarifies to them his method of rule. He will have utter allegiance to the city from its citizens and military. All other relationships come second. To that end, he explains his proclamation that Polyneices not be buried: it is the proper punishment for one who raised arms against the city.
But on the first night, a Sentry enters, disheveled, confused, fearful, and hesitant to tell what he knows. He finally explains that Polyneices body was sprinkled with earth-- enough to show that a burial ceremony had been performed. The guards argued over who was at fault-- all declaring profusely that they were innocent-- before he was chosen to bring the news to Creon. Creon, in turn, is apoplectic. A soldier suggests it might be the work of one of the gods, but Creon declares that Polyneices was certainly not deserving of such an honor. He decides that the guards around the body must have been bribed into allowing this to happen, and directs the Sentry to discover who defied his orders. The Sentry protests, and Creon leaves in disgust. Alone, the Sentry vows that he shall not return-- it's not worth the hassle.
----------------------------
The language here seems to be more... regal than in the Ajax. I suppose that is in keeping with the characters we've met, who are of royal station. But it might just be Roche being careful about that sort of thing (he did give the Sentry a Cockney accent to contrast with Creon).
There was a very quick, but useful, introduction of the overall conflict of the play: duty to family vs. duty to state. Creon explicitly demands utter and complete loyalty to the state, even under penalty of death. But implicit in this is the idea that the threat of violence is needed to maintain the loyalty to the state-- and that will have no effect on those willing to martyr themselves over their loyalty to family, as Antigone expressly states that she is.
Thebes's soldiers (the Chorus) enter, bragging loudly over their victory. Creon enters and clarifies to them his method of rule. He will have utter allegiance to the city from its citizens and military. All other relationships come second. To that end, he explains his proclamation that Polyneices not be buried: it is the proper punishment for one who raised arms against the city.
But on the first night, a Sentry enters, disheveled, confused, fearful, and hesitant to tell what he knows. He finally explains that Polyneices body was sprinkled with earth-- enough to show that a burial ceremony had been performed. The guards argued over who was at fault-- all declaring profusely that they were innocent-- before he was chosen to bring the news to Creon. Creon, in turn, is apoplectic. A soldier suggests it might be the work of one of the gods, but Creon declares that Polyneices was certainly not deserving of such an honor. He decides that the guards around the body must have been bribed into allowing this to happen, and directs the Sentry to discover who defied his orders. The Sentry protests, and Creon leaves in disgust. Alone, the Sentry vows that he shall not return-- it's not worth the hassle.
----------------------------
The language here seems to be more... regal than in the Ajax. I suppose that is in keeping with the characters we've met, who are of royal station. But it might just be Roche being careful about that sort of thing (he did give the Sentry a Cockney accent to contrast with Creon).
There was a very quick, but useful, introduction of the overall conflict of the play: duty to family vs. duty to state. Creon explicitly demands utter and complete loyalty to the state, even under penalty of death. But implicit in this is the idea that the threat of violence is needed to maintain the loyalty to the state-- and that will have no effect on those willing to martyr themselves over their loyalty to family, as Antigone expressly states that she is.
Saturday, May 28, 2011
Heretics, V - Mr. H.G. Wells And The Giants
It is our duty to those we call hypocrites to closely examine their beliefs, and thereby to perhaps discover the utter sincerity with which they hold them. This applies most pertinently to the deeply religious of the past, who (we say) professed "crawling humility" and yet (somehow, we sneer) gained control over the whole world. There is nothing hypocritical about this-- in fact, the former certainly opens the door to the latter. By properly claiming that they deserved nothing, the Christians opened the way to achieving everything; by not always examining whether they had been slighted, those Christians opened themselves to immeasurable (because unmeasured!) gains.
A modern example of the same phenomenon of genuine humility is the truly great scientist. He becomes great through his attention and devotion to a single small idea-- whose consequence is to completely overturn our understanding of the world. It is the quiet devotion that achieves this, though, not the bombastic bragging over the enormous consequences. "There were possible answers to Huxley; there was no answer possible to Darwin." One specific example of this kind of humility is H.G. Wells. His literary output is utterly fantastic-- but he comes to it from careful and sincere examination of the state of humanity around him. Proof that he is no huckster: the softening of his futuristic vision from that of Morlock and Eloi to that of competent, knowledgeable citizens.
In another instance, he has abandoned his view that reproduction will become a matter of managed breeding of superior men. He has come to view such a program as technically infeasible. It is, instead, morally infeasible more than that-- good men will never allow themselves to be treated in this way. The problem that he does not perceive, ultimately, is that he views health as a problem to be scientifically or medically managed-- hence, health care. This is the opposite of the truth. True health is that state in which we can afford to be bold, daring, striving, ambitious, and reckless. The healthy man eats to fill his appetite and takes pleasure in doing so; exercises primarily to enjoy exertion and the outdoors; marries for love! The other results-- stronger, well-operating bodies and offspring-- take care of themselves.
Wells's devotion to a scientific approach leaves him with other blind spots as well. His view of man starts with the material, when any simple examination shows you must start with the spiritual. His vision of Utopia is built first on its citizens' shunning the concept of original sin-- but a simple examination shows this to be the most self-evident concept we have! "He would have found... that a permanent possibility of selfishness arises from the mere fact of having a self[.]" Every venture into Utopia suffers from the same defect, of course-- that of assuming the big problems have gone away, and organizing society to deal with the small. "They first assume that no man will want more than his share, and then are very ingenious in explaining whether his share will be devlibered by motor-car or balloon." But this Utopia is impossible because man's devotion to his ideals-- to the point of fighting for them-- is his defining characterisitic.
The scientific devotion leads to the shunning of metaphysics, and so to ridiculing a belief in or fixation on ideals and universals. But such an attitude implicitly rejects the possibility of knowledge in the first place. You cannot say we have left our silly theories behind and have moved to more solid and reasonable foundation of knowledge unless there is a direct relationship between the old and the new; unless there is an ideal state of knowledge that both participate in, the new in greater measure than the old; unless there be a commonality through which we make the valid comparison. Noticing a difference necessarily comes after noticing a similarity-- otherwise, why make the comparison at all? "When we say the hare moves faster, we say that the toroise moves. And when we say of a thing that it moves, we say, without need of other words, that there are things that do not move. And even in the act of saying that things change, we say that there is something unchangeable." Put another way: yes, surely North and South are relative concepts, but the very idea of direction requires that there be a fixed North Pole. We say that one object is dimmer or brighter than another-- but we are only able to do so coherently because we have a fixed idea of absolute light against which we compare them.
And so Wells's sociological speculations suffer from the defect of his metaphysical incoherence. In one book, he examines (like Shaw) the Nietschzian idea of the Superman. If the Superman is truly beyond the comprehension of men, they will react to him with simple indifference. [Is our reaction to, for instance, the weather any different?] It is only if a valid comparison to common men can be recognized that they will react to the Superman with awe or devotion. And that comparison will always be made according to the same standards. Jack's Giant may have viewed himself as a kind of Superman, but the only question for Jack was whether the Giant was good. The fundamental measure, and hence the central characteristic, of man is moralness-- a spiritual quality.
And in other ways, hypothesizing a devotion to a proposed Superman misidentifies the essence of man. We value courage, but courage is not a quality possessed by a Superman. Rather, courage is a quality shown by the small man in challenging the Superman.
And, "If the Superman is better than we, of course we need not fight him; but in that case, why not call him the Saint?"
This fixation on the Superman who is beyond human is only a modern development. Our ancient heroes were, instead, simply more human-- and that in their superior display of the central characteristics of humanity. Achilles is heroic because his deeds on the battlefield emerge from his love of his fallen friend. We cheer even the peasant who challenges Robin Hood when he grows too full of himself. The hope of humanity is in the dignity and self-possession of the underdog. It will be ever thus. Utopia will have to wait.
------------------------
Wow. This chapter is a tour de force.
Irony alert: Chesterton writes of the passing of the great scientific period-- in 1905. The new advances in relativity and quantum dynamics were right on the doorstep. It is interesting, though, that Einstein seemed to possess the same qualities that Chesterton admired in the great scientists: devotion to a simple idea, and the careful working out of the consequences.
On the other hand, we currently seem to be in a lull in the advance of fundamental science. And yet, we do see self-aggrandizement on the part of those who wield scientific authority. Look at the grand (and ever-changing, and ever-magnifying) predictions made by climate science in the popular press. And the response of many is to tune them out, or to fight back. Einstein didn't make political hay out of relativity.
What a wake-up call in Chesterton's diagnosis of the "health care" problem, even in his own time! The mistake is-- still!-- in thinking that health is an ever-present problem needing daily management. It is not. Prudence demands planning and insuring against catastrophe. Between emergencies, health is a condition to be celebrated, or a state to be simply maintained.
In his discussion of Utopia, Chesterton hits on the fundamental flaw in the liberal project: imagining that humanity's problems might be ultimately "solved", but only through a fundamental change in the essential character of man. It imagines that man's vices-- greed, ambition, selfishness-- might be expunged, while simultaneously mischaracterizing man's virtues-- especially an individual's sense of self-worth-- as dangerous problems to be tamped down. Ultimately, the thought that man can be manipulated stems from a rejection that there even is such a thing as human nature-- which either stems from or leads to the thought that there are no fundamental natures in anything at all. Then, the problems that the meddler is trying to solve are problems only in the sense that they violate the observer's personal sense of justice-- and the meddling instinct stems from the egoistic assumption that that personal sense is sacrosanct.
A modern example of the same phenomenon of genuine humility is the truly great scientist. He becomes great through his attention and devotion to a single small idea-- whose consequence is to completely overturn our understanding of the world. It is the quiet devotion that achieves this, though, not the bombastic bragging over the enormous consequences. "There were possible answers to Huxley; there was no answer possible to Darwin." One specific example of this kind of humility is H.G. Wells. His literary output is utterly fantastic-- but he comes to it from careful and sincere examination of the state of humanity around him. Proof that he is no huckster: the softening of his futuristic vision from that of Morlock and Eloi to that of competent, knowledgeable citizens.
In another instance, he has abandoned his view that reproduction will become a matter of managed breeding of superior men. He has come to view such a program as technically infeasible. It is, instead, morally infeasible more than that-- good men will never allow themselves to be treated in this way. The problem that he does not perceive, ultimately, is that he views health as a problem to be scientifically or medically managed-- hence, health care. This is the opposite of the truth. True health is that state in which we can afford to be bold, daring, striving, ambitious, and reckless. The healthy man eats to fill his appetite and takes pleasure in doing so; exercises primarily to enjoy exertion and the outdoors; marries for love! The other results-- stronger, well-operating bodies and offspring-- take care of themselves.
Wells's devotion to a scientific approach leaves him with other blind spots as well. His view of man starts with the material, when any simple examination shows you must start with the spiritual. His vision of Utopia is built first on its citizens' shunning the concept of original sin-- but a simple examination shows this to be the most self-evident concept we have! "He would have found... that a permanent possibility of selfishness arises from the mere fact of having a self[.]" Every venture into Utopia suffers from the same defect, of course-- that of assuming the big problems have gone away, and organizing society to deal with the small. "They first assume that no man will want more than his share, and then are very ingenious in explaining whether his share will be devlibered by motor-car or balloon." But this Utopia is impossible because man's devotion to his ideals-- to the point of fighting for them-- is his defining characterisitic.
The scientific devotion leads to the shunning of metaphysics, and so to ridiculing a belief in or fixation on ideals and universals. But such an attitude implicitly rejects the possibility of knowledge in the first place. You cannot say we have left our silly theories behind and have moved to more solid and reasonable foundation of knowledge unless there is a direct relationship between the old and the new; unless there is an ideal state of knowledge that both participate in, the new in greater measure than the old; unless there be a commonality through which we make the valid comparison. Noticing a difference necessarily comes after noticing a similarity-- otherwise, why make the comparison at all? "When we say the hare moves faster, we say that the toroise moves. And when we say of a thing that it moves, we say, without need of other words, that there are things that do not move. And even in the act of saying that things change, we say that there is something unchangeable." Put another way: yes, surely North and South are relative concepts, but the very idea of direction requires that there be a fixed North Pole. We say that one object is dimmer or brighter than another-- but we are only able to do so coherently because we have a fixed idea of absolute light against which we compare them.
And so Wells's sociological speculations suffer from the defect of his metaphysical incoherence. In one book, he examines (like Shaw) the Nietschzian idea of the Superman. If the Superman is truly beyond the comprehension of men, they will react to him with simple indifference. [Is our reaction to, for instance, the weather any different?] It is only if a valid comparison to common men can be recognized that they will react to the Superman with awe or devotion. And that comparison will always be made according to the same standards. Jack's Giant may have viewed himself as a kind of Superman, but the only question for Jack was whether the Giant was good. The fundamental measure, and hence the central characteristic, of man is moralness-- a spiritual quality.
And in other ways, hypothesizing a devotion to a proposed Superman misidentifies the essence of man. We value courage, but courage is not a quality possessed by a Superman. Rather, courage is a quality shown by the small man in challenging the Superman.
And, "If the Superman is better than we, of course we need not fight him; but in that case, why not call him the Saint?"
This fixation on the Superman who is beyond human is only a modern development. Our ancient heroes were, instead, simply more human-- and that in their superior display of the central characteristics of humanity. Achilles is heroic because his deeds on the battlefield emerge from his love of his fallen friend. We cheer even the peasant who challenges Robin Hood when he grows too full of himself. The hope of humanity is in the dignity and self-possession of the underdog. It will be ever thus. Utopia will have to wait.
------------------------
Wow. This chapter is a tour de force.
Irony alert: Chesterton writes of the passing of the great scientific period-- in 1905. The new advances in relativity and quantum dynamics were right on the doorstep. It is interesting, though, that Einstein seemed to possess the same qualities that Chesterton admired in the great scientists: devotion to a simple idea, and the careful working out of the consequences.
On the other hand, we currently seem to be in a lull in the advance of fundamental science. And yet, we do see self-aggrandizement on the part of those who wield scientific authority. Look at the grand (and ever-changing, and ever-magnifying) predictions made by climate science in the popular press. And the response of many is to tune them out, or to fight back. Einstein didn't make political hay out of relativity.
What a wake-up call in Chesterton's diagnosis of the "health care" problem, even in his own time! The mistake is-- still!-- in thinking that health is an ever-present problem needing daily management. It is not. Prudence demands planning and insuring against catastrophe. Between emergencies, health is a condition to be celebrated, or a state to be simply maintained.
In his discussion of Utopia, Chesterton hits on the fundamental flaw in the liberal project: imagining that humanity's problems might be ultimately "solved", but only through a fundamental change in the essential character of man. It imagines that man's vices-- greed, ambition, selfishness-- might be expunged, while simultaneously mischaracterizing man's virtues-- especially an individual's sense of self-worth-- as dangerous problems to be tamped down. Ultimately, the thought that man can be manipulated stems from a rejection that there even is such a thing as human nature-- which either stems from or leads to the thought that there are no fundamental natures in anything at all. Then, the problems that the meddler is trying to solve are problems only in the sense that they violate the observer's personal sense of justice-- and the meddling instinct stems from the egoistic assumption that that personal sense is sacrosanct.
Sunday, May 22, 2011
Ajax, 4
Menelaus arrives and decrees that the body should not be buried-- Ajax should be treated as an enemy with all the penalty that entails for his plan to murder the Greek leaders. Further, his greater crime is insubordination against his superiors. A city cannot thrive unless the citizens submit to authority and recognize their betters; an army cannot survive unless the soldiery submit absolutely to their commanders. It was Ajax's great fault that he never did this.
Teucer angrily rebuts. Ajax did not join the war as a soldier under Menelaus; Ajax was not even a subject under the region of Menelaus's kingdom. Ajax always acted as a free man-- and his greatness in battle was a testament to this self-regard. Rising anger as Menelaus and Teucer shout back-and-forth, each pleading his case: Menelaus saying there must be penalty for his crime, Teucer retorting that no crime was actually committed-- except perhaps denying Ajax the prize that was deservedly his. Menelaus slinks away looking for backup.
Teucer hastily begins the burial process, with the help of of Tecmessa and Eurysaces. Instructs Eurysaces to cling to the body-- no intruder would dare separate the two of them. Agamemnon arrives to tell of Teucer, with a much firmer and angrier tone than Menelaus. He rightly claims authority as Ajax's general in battle-- so Teucer's previous arguments have less weight. He also hurls personal insults about Ajax's questionable lineage (through his captive mother), putting him in his place as a subordinate to the great leaders around him. But Teucer comes back even more directly and forthrightly than before-- reminding Agamemnon of Ajax's brave defense of the ships, of his eagerness to face off against Hector alone, and of Agamemnon's own questionable lineage through his father Atreus's evil actions. It's ugly.
Odysseus arrives, and quickly (and calmly) says Ajax ought to be buried-- even offering to assist in the burial. His reasons are many-- he recognizes Ajax's previous greatness, he recognizes the slight he experienced, he knows he has own enemies who could try to impose the same insult after his own death, and Agamemnon (like a politician looking to save face) can claim a spirit of generosity back among the men he leads. Agamemnon, not happy about it, concedes. Ultimately, Teucer takes on the burial himself, for he knows that Ajax and Odysseus were true enemies; Odysseus acquiesces and leaves. The body is carried off.
------------------------------
Teucer is awesome. Two amazing speeches. First, an exchange with Menelaus (1143-1158):
Teucer angrily rebuts. Ajax did not join the war as a soldier under Menelaus; Ajax was not even a subject under the region of Menelaus's kingdom. Ajax always acted as a free man-- and his greatness in battle was a testament to this self-regard. Rising anger as Menelaus and Teucer shout back-and-forth, each pleading his case: Menelaus saying there must be penalty for his crime, Teucer retorting that no crime was actually committed-- except perhaps denying Ajax the prize that was deservedly his. Menelaus slinks away looking for backup.
Teucer hastily begins the burial process, with the help of of Tecmessa and Eurysaces. Instructs Eurysaces to cling to the body-- no intruder would dare separate the two of them. Agamemnon arrives to tell of Teucer, with a much firmer and angrier tone than Menelaus. He rightly claims authority as Ajax's general in battle-- so Teucer's previous arguments have less weight. He also hurls personal insults about Ajax's questionable lineage (through his captive mother), putting him in his place as a subordinate to the great leaders around him. But Teucer comes back even more directly and forthrightly than before-- reminding Agamemnon of Ajax's brave defense of the ships, of his eagerness to face off against Hector alone, and of Agamemnon's own questionable lineage through his father Atreus's evil actions. It's ugly.
Odysseus arrives, and quickly (and calmly) says Ajax ought to be buried-- even offering to assist in the burial. His reasons are many-- he recognizes Ajax's previous greatness, he recognizes the slight he experienced, he knows he has own enemies who could try to impose the same insult after his own death, and Agamemnon (like a politician looking to save face) can claim a spirit of generosity back among the men he leads. Agamemnon, not happy about it, concedes. Ultimately, Teucer takes on the burial himself, for he knows that Ajax and Odysseus were true enemies; Odysseus acquiesces and leaves. The body is carried off.
------------------------------
Teucer is awesome. Two amazing speeches. First, an exchange with Menelaus (1143-1158):
Menelaus: I observed a man once of fast and saucy speechThen, he tells off Agamemnon in the most devastating way possible (1266-1314)
Who had pressed sailors to make a voyage in a storm;
When the weather got really rough, you couldn't hear
Him piping anywhere: he hid himself in his cloak,
And anybody aboard could step on him at will.
And very possibly you and your reckless speech--
If a big whistling storm should suddenly come
Out of a little cloud-- your clamorous uproar
Might be quenched in a very similar fashion.
Teucer: And I once saw a man inflated with foolishness,
Who insulted the misfortunes of his neighbors.
And another man, closely resembling me,
Quite like me in temperament, gave him a straight look
And said to him, "Man, don't outrage the dead.
You certainly shall regret it if you do."
That was the advice he gave that worthless man.
I see him now, and he is, it seems to me,
You, and nobody else. Am I speaking in riddles?
Alas! How fugitive is the gratitudeLove the references to the stuff I've already read. It's working!
Men owe the dead, how soon shown to deceive!
This man has no trifling remembrance,
Ajax, of you, though oftentimes for him
You risked your life and bore the stress of war.
All that is gone now, easily tossed away.
You, who just now spoke that long, foolish speech,
Can't you remember any more at all
How you were penned once close behind your picket,
And all but ruined in the rout of war
With flames licking the ships' quarter-decks
Already, and Hector high in the air, leaping
Over the fosse to board, but Ajax came,
Alone, to save you? Who fended off that ruin?
Wasn't it he, the very man you now
Declare fought nowhere but where you fought too?
What do you say? Did he deal fairly then?
And when that other time he closed alone
In single fight with Hector, not conscripted,
But chosen when each champion put his lot
Into the crested helmet-- Ajax then
Put in no shirking lot among the rest,
No clod of moist earth, no! but one to skip
Lightly, first and victorious, from the helm.
It was he that did those things, and I stood by him:
The slave, yes! the barbarian mother's son!
Wretched man, why do you light upon that taunt?
Aren't you aware that your own grandfather,
Old Pelops, was a barbarous Phrygian? Or
That Atreus, yes, your actual father, set
Before his brother a most unholy dish
Of his own sons' flesh? And you yourself
Had a Cretan for your mother, in whose bed
An interloping foreigner was discovered,
And she consigned, and by her parent's order,
To drown among the fishes of the deep.
These are your origins. Can you censure mine?
Telamon was my father, and he won
My mother as his valorous prize of war.
She was a princess by her birth, the child
Of King Laomedon, and Heracles
Distinguished her to be my father's gift.
Two royal races gave me to the world.
How shall I shame my kin if I defend them
In their adversity, when you with shameless words
Would fling them out unburied? Listen to this:
If you should venture to cast Ajax out,
You must cast out the three of us as well,
Together in one heap with him. I make my choice
To stand in public and to die for him,
Rather than for your wife-- or was it your brother's wife?
So! Think of your own case, and no merely mine;
For if you vex me, you may wish you had been
a coward, rather than too bold with me.
Saturday, May 21, 2011
Ajax, 3
A messenger comes with news. Teucer arrived at the Greek camp and was scolded and abused over the rumors of Ajax's crime. The messenger brings the instruction that Ajax is to be kept in his tent for the remainder of the day. The seer Calchas has said that his raving lunacy is due to the influence of Athena, and is only temporary. It is punishment for Ajax's overconfidence and pride, first expressed to his father when he initially left for battle, and recently boasted to Athena herself when Ajax shunned her help and declared his self-sufficient strength. The news throws the Chorus and Tecmessa into a panic, and they split up into search parties to locate Ajax before tragedy strikes.
Ajax, alone by the beach, prepares his sword in the ground so that he may fall on it. He makes his final peace and pleas with the gods. To Zeus: that Teucer might find his body first and protect it from desecration. To Hermes, that the death may be swift. To the Furies, that they may ensure a similar end to Agamemnon and Menelaus. To Helios, that he may shine on his homeland and parents. His final farewell is to his home country. Ajax slays himself.
The search parties reunite, and it is Tecmess who finds the body. Wailing. The Chorus sees that Ajax had fooled them with his farewell talk before. They speak of revenge against the enemies in the Greek army who drove Ajax to do this, with special anger toward Athena and her favoritism of Odysseus. None appreciated Ajax while he lived.
Teucer arrives and vows to protect the body. He summons for Ajax's son and vows protection for him, too. He laments his own inability to forestall this-- and dreads returning home and living under the quiet anger that will surely come from his father, Telamon. He recognizes a singular irony: the great enemy warriors Hector and Ajax exchanged weapons and armor under friendly terms. Hector was then done in when he was dragged from a chariot by Ajax's girdle; Ajax killed himself on Hector's sword. There must be a plan of the gods guiding all these events.
The Chorus and Teucer hear an approach and swiftly hide the body. Menelaus arrives.
Ajax, alone by the beach, prepares his sword in the ground so that he may fall on it. He makes his final peace and pleas with the gods. To Zeus: that Teucer might find his body first and protect it from desecration. To Hermes, that the death may be swift. To the Furies, that they may ensure a similar end to Agamemnon and Menelaus. To Helios, that he may shine on his homeland and parents. His final farewell is to his home country. Ajax slays himself.
The search parties reunite, and it is Tecmess who finds the body. Wailing. The Chorus sees that Ajax had fooled them with his farewell talk before. They speak of revenge against the enemies in the Greek army who drove Ajax to do this, with special anger toward Athena and her favoritism of Odysseus. None appreciated Ajax while he lived.
Teucer arrives and vows to protect the body. He summons for Ajax's son and vows protection for him, too. He laments his own inability to forestall this-- and dreads returning home and living under the quiet anger that will surely come from his father, Telamon. He recognizes a singular irony: the great enemy warriors Hector and Ajax exchanged weapons and armor under friendly terms. Hector was then done in when he was dragged from a chariot by Ajax's girdle; Ajax killed himself on Hector's sword. There must be a plan of the gods guiding all these events.
The Chorus and Teucer hear an approach and swiftly hide the body. Menelaus arrives.
Ajax, 2
Ajax emerges, now sane, but distraught, while the Chorus and Tecmessa look on, terrified. He lashes out at all who have slighted him-- especially Odysseus, Agamemnon, and Menelaus. He feels abandoned by the gods, disgusted by the war, unappreciated by the army, resentful of his hero father whose standard he can no longer fulfill. He cannot return home in shame. He considers going out in a blaze of glory on a suicide charge into the Trojans, but thinks that will give the sons of Atreus too much pleasure. He is utterly broken.
Tecmessa attempts to bring him back from the brink. Life surely has more in store-- look at her own improvement after her household had been destroyed! He owes it to her, and to his mother and father, and his son, to push through the misery and pain.
Ajax calls for his son, to give him his final advice, and states his final testament. He bestows his great shield, but says his other weaponry must be buried with him-- they will not be distributed among the Greeks, now his enemies. His son Eurysaces will be raised by Ajax's brother, Teucer. The business done, he shuts himself away.
The Chorus is in more of a panic than ever. But Ajax emerges, and announces his next move. The closeness of death has softened his edge, he says. He does not want to die. Let his weapons be buried, as asked. Meanwhile, he will go to the sea to do penance to the gods. He will submit to the Greek kings-- it is the honorable and dutiful thing to do. He goes. The Chorus is ecstatic. Wisdom has prevailed. They celebrate the turn in his behavior, and look forward only to positive outcomes ahead.
-----------------------
Of course, we're only halfway through the play. Things are bound to get worse.
I was hoping to see Ajax go through the classic five stages of grief-- couldn't find it, though. At least, no clear instance of Bargaining.
I was surprised to see the daddy issues crop up here. But it reminded me of that other classic of the Western literary tradition:
Tecmessa attempts to bring him back from the brink. Life surely has more in store-- look at her own improvement after her household had been destroyed! He owes it to her, and to his mother and father, and his son, to push through the misery and pain.
Ajax calls for his son, to give him his final advice, and states his final testament. He bestows his great shield, but says his other weaponry must be buried with him-- they will not be distributed among the Greeks, now his enemies. His son Eurysaces will be raised by Ajax's brother, Teucer. The business done, he shuts himself away.
The Chorus is in more of a panic than ever. But Ajax emerges, and announces his next move. The closeness of death has softened his edge, he says. He does not want to die. Let his weapons be buried, as asked. Meanwhile, he will go to the sea to do penance to the gods. He will submit to the Greek kings-- it is the honorable and dutiful thing to do. He goes. The Chorus is ecstatic. Wisdom has prevailed. They celebrate the turn in his behavior, and look forward only to positive outcomes ahead.
-----------------------
Of course, we're only halfway through the play. Things are bound to get worse.
I was hoping to see Ajax go through the classic five stages of grief-- couldn't find it, though. At least, no clear instance of Bargaining.
I was surprised to see the daddy issues crop up here. But it reminded me of that other classic of the Western literary tradition:
Let's see. Emilio Estevez as Ajax, Ally Sheedy as Tecmessa, Anthony Michael Hall as the Chorus, John Bender as Odysseus, and Principal Vernon as Agamemnon Menelaus. With special guest Larry Lester's Buns as the slaughtered animals.
I think I may have something here.
(Note for future reference: I actually just wanted the clip where Emilio Estevez starts crying about his old man telling him to be a winner. That clip doesn't exist on YouTube. This "Andy Tribute" montage is soooooo much better.)
(Note for future reference: I actually just wanted the clip where Emilio Estevez starts crying about his old man telling him to be a winner. That clip doesn't exist on YouTube. This "Andy Tribute" montage is soooooo much better.)
Friday, May 20, 2011
Ajax, 1
Odysseus stealthily approaches Ajax's tent, investigating a bizarre crime. It seems that Ajax has raided the Greeks' livestock pen, murdering its guards and slaughtering many animals, as well as bringing a few back to his tent for further torture and carnage. Athena stops Odysseus and explains what really happened: in retaliation for being denied Achilleus's armor, Ajax meant to kill Odysseus, Agamemnon, Menelaus, and many other officers, so Athena put him in a frenzy and directed him to the livestock instead. Odysseus is taken aback even more than before, when he only thought he knew had happened.
The Chorus, made up of Ajax's men, approach in fear and horror, having heard terrible rumors about their leader. They try to make excuses and otherwise explain away the behavior, anything to avoid the truth of what has happened. Tecmessa (Ajax's wife through capture) emerges and tells them what she knows-- the terrible madness that consumed Ajax, and his singular mindset to slaughter the animals he slaughtered. It appears, however, that he is emerging from the crazed state. The men are glad to hear it, but Tecmessa explains that that makes things worse than before: whereas at least Ajax was pleased with himself in his frenzy, now he has fallen into misery with the rest. He is now wailing in agony inside the tent.
----------------------
A very interesting narrative device: we get a picture of the action that has taken place from the perspective of five different characters-- Odysseus, Athena, Ajax, the Chorus, and Tecmessa-- none of whom really understand what has happened (except Athena, I suppose). Instead, rumors are flying. It's a frightening (in the sense of disorienting) introduction to the play.
To that end, this passage is a wonderful exploration of how rumors spread, and how political factions batten down the hatches to try to protect their own. From the Chorus (148-182):
The Chorus, made up of Ajax's men, approach in fear and horror, having heard terrible rumors about their leader. They try to make excuses and otherwise explain away the behavior, anything to avoid the truth of what has happened. Tecmessa (Ajax's wife through capture) emerges and tells them what she knows-- the terrible madness that consumed Ajax, and his singular mindset to slaughter the animals he slaughtered. It appears, however, that he is emerging from the crazed state. The men are glad to hear it, but Tecmessa explains that that makes things worse than before: whereas at least Ajax was pleased with himself in his frenzy, now he has fallen into misery with the rest. He is now wailing in agony inside the tent.
----------------------
A very interesting narrative device: we get a picture of the action that has taken place from the perspective of five different characters-- Odysseus, Athena, Ajax, the Chorus, and Tecmessa-- none of whom really understand what has happened (except Athena, I suppose). Instead, rumors are flying. It's a frightening (in the sense of disorienting) introduction to the play.
To that end, this passage is a wonderful exploration of how rumors spread, and how political factions batten down the hatches to try to protect their own. From the Chorus (148-182):
Such tales as these, whisperings and fabrications,Also of note: this is my first explanation of what was going on here, when Homer only hinted at the rivalry between Odysseus and Aias. (And they seemed so chummy in the Iliad!) It struck me how amazing it would have been to have all these tales and myths swirling around as the foundation of the common culture. Here I am trying to re-read it all, but there is so much that is missing and lost. Oh, well.
Odysseus is supplying to every ear.
And many believe him. For as he speaks of you,
His words win credit, and each new hearer
More than the teller relishes his chance
To insult at your distress.
Strike at a great man, and you will not miss:
But if one should bend such slander at me,
None would believe him. Envy stalks
After magnates of wealth and power...
Can it have been wild, bull-consorting Artemis
That stirred you, evil Tale...
Or was it Enyalios, the bronze-cased Lord of War
That blamed our lord's co-operant spear,
And spitefully paid him out in the night's error?
For never, son of Telamon, of your own heart's prompting
Would you so far have strayed...
Thursday, May 19, 2011
Sophocles
A bit of research shows that only seven of Sophocles' 123 plays have survived. Somehow, I managed to collect the whole set. Huzzah!
The first book contains Ajax, The Women of Trachis, Electra, and Philoctetes. Translations are by John Moore, Michael Jameson, and David Greene-- all unknown to me, so I'm keeping my fingers crossed. I'm pretty sure I originally bought this for my freshman seminar, but it's possible that I got it for my Ancient Philosophy course at the University of Chicago, along with the Iliad. In either case, I can't remember actually reading anything out of it. Shame on me.
The second book contains the Theban plays: Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus, and Antigone. I picked this up at Half Price Books when I bought my Aeschylus. Translations are by Paul Roche again. Solid.
The overall chronology of authorship, it seems, is Ajax - Antigone - Women of Trachis - Oedipus the King - Electra - Philoctetes - Oedipus at Colonus, so that's the order I'm going in. That means I'm reading the book with the Theban plays out of order, but they weren't written together anyway, so what's the dif? We'll see what Roche's introduction has to say about it, though.
Incidentally, what I do remember from freshman seminar is watching a bizarre video in the library on a crummy VHS and old tube TV starring Morgan Freeman in some sort of retelling of the Oedipus saga in a church or something. (Which would seem to imply that I got the first Sophocles book there-- but that book doesn't have the Oedipus plays in it. So now I don't know what happened.) Anyway, I finally managed to track down what in the hell that was all about. Feast your eyes on "The Gospel at Colonus" starring, indeed, Morgan Freeman.
The first book contains Ajax, The Women of Trachis, Electra, and Philoctetes. Translations are by John Moore, Michael Jameson, and David Greene-- all unknown to me, so I'm keeping my fingers crossed. I'm pretty sure I originally bought this for my freshman seminar, but it's possible that I got it for my Ancient Philosophy course at the University of Chicago, along with the Iliad. In either case, I can't remember actually reading anything out of it. Shame on me.
The second book contains the Theban plays: Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus, and Antigone. I picked this up at Half Price Books when I bought my Aeschylus. Translations are by Paul Roche again. Solid.
The overall chronology of authorship, it seems, is Ajax - Antigone - Women of Trachis - Oedipus the King - Electra - Philoctetes - Oedipus at Colonus, so that's the order I'm going in. That means I'm reading the book with the Theban plays out of order, but they weren't written together anyway, so what's the dif? We'll see what Roche's introduction has to say about it, though.
Incidentally, what I do remember from freshman seminar is watching a bizarre video in the library on a crummy VHS and old tube TV starring Morgan Freeman in some sort of retelling of the Oedipus saga in a church or something. (Which would seem to imply that I got the first Sophocles book there-- but that book doesn't have the Oedipus plays in it. So now I don't know what happened.) Anyway, I finally managed to track down what in the hell that was all about. Feast your eyes on "The Gospel at Colonus" starring, indeed, Morgan Freeman.
Well this is just depressing
Review of a critic of Classics translations (via The Fortnightly Review). Apparently, Lattimore sucks.
To which I can only say
To which I can only say
Monday, May 09, 2011
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, XVIII - XIX
XVIII (Of Tyranny) - When those placed in positions of power use their authority to enrich themselves rather than directing their actions to the good of the people, that is tyranny. It can be opposed, but make sure only to oppose by force actual injustice. Things to watch out for: take care not to tear down an entire edifice of government, which might be saved, over the actions of a single bad actor; try to work through the law and the still-functioning parts of government to take down a tyrant; don't make things worse for everybody by invoking force. But in extreme situations, bold action is indeed needed. So...
XIX (Of the Dissolution of Government) - The actual dissolution of government does not necessarilly entail the dissolution of society. It's possible, in the case of war, that the destruction be so complete that the remaining men are reduced to wandering or making their way by joining new societies. But more often the dissolution of a government structure is actually the act of a functioning society, a society that maintains its identity and unity through the transition and into the future government to whom they give their revised consent.
Dissolution of government happens when the legislature is unable or unwilling to fulfill its duties; or when the executive absolutely refuses to be subservient to the legislature, and thereby does injustice to the people at large.
In such rare circumstances, when legal remedies within the existing government won't rectify the situation, rebellion is necessary. It is not to be taken lightly. It is in all cases a perillous position to be in. It represents, in essence, a state of war between the people and those to whom they granted authority. Often, we call those rebels to task for their actions-- but that rebellion is a two-way street. It is equally legitimate to call the leaders rebellious who have exceeded their mandates, or forgotton their duties, or lost sight of the good of the people with which they have been entrusted. In this state of war, when legitimately established, there is no supreme side with power over the subservient other; both parties are placed on an equal footing. And in the end, it is always up to the judgment of the people as a whole which side will prevail, and on which principles the government will reestablish its footing going forward.
---------------------------
So don't play around with accusations of tyranny. It's serious business.
Glad I read all this. I don't think it hurt that I forced myself to read it so quickly. There's a lot of background assumptions and principles it was good for me to see laid out so carefully. I'm sure most of the political readings and writings I do will refer back to these principles, if only implicitly. I do think Locke has a good, solid insight into human nature and how that informs political relationships. (But I would say that.)
XIX (Of the Dissolution of Government) - The actual dissolution of government does not necessarilly entail the dissolution of society. It's possible, in the case of war, that the destruction be so complete that the remaining men are reduced to wandering or making their way by joining new societies. But more often the dissolution of a government structure is actually the act of a functioning society, a society that maintains its identity and unity through the transition and into the future government to whom they give their revised consent.
Dissolution of government happens when the legislature is unable or unwilling to fulfill its duties; or when the executive absolutely refuses to be subservient to the legislature, and thereby does injustice to the people at large.
In such rare circumstances, when legal remedies within the existing government won't rectify the situation, rebellion is necessary. It is not to be taken lightly. It is in all cases a perillous position to be in. It represents, in essence, a state of war between the people and those to whom they granted authority. Often, we call those rebels to task for their actions-- but that rebellion is a two-way street. It is equally legitimate to call the leaders rebellious who have exceeded their mandates, or forgotton their duties, or lost sight of the good of the people with which they have been entrusted. In this state of war, when legitimately established, there is no supreme side with power over the subservient other; both parties are placed on an equal footing. And in the end, it is always up to the judgment of the people as a whole which side will prevail, and on which principles the government will reestablish its footing going forward.
---------------------------
So don't play around with accusations of tyranny. It's serious business.
Glad I read all this. I don't think it hurt that I forced myself to read it so quickly. There's a lot of background assumptions and principles it was good for me to see laid out so carefully. I'm sure most of the political readings and writings I do will refer back to these principles, if only implicitly. I do think Locke has a good, solid insight into human nature and how that informs political relationships. (But I would say that.)
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, XVI - XVII
XVI (Of Conquest) - It is thought that the role of government is to wage war and conquer neighboring lands. This is not so. For starters, a government that conquers a people can never set up a legitimate ruling legislator, for they would surely act without the consent of the newly governed.
But in the case of a nation that wins a war lawfully against an aggressor, what are the obligations? The conquerer gains no more authority over his own people than before-- no aggrandizement allowed. Over the conquered people, he has no authority if they did not participate nor acquiesce in the aggression-- an illegal war perpetrated by leaders can't be assumed to be through the consent of the people. It is true that the conquerer has a right to property to repair the injustice done to him. But this right does not extend to depriving women and children of the property they inherit from their-- even their wicked-- husbands and fathers. In these cases the men never had the power to risk their wives' and children's property to begin with, so it cannot be forfeited.
The conquerer does not have the right to impose a new system of government without the consent of the people, either. It is true that they must impose some restrictions, to ensure justice for their own injury. But this imposition has no force on the children in that nation, who retain the natural right to establish, through their own consent, their own system of government upon coming of age. To prevent this is its own injustice.
XVII (Of Usurpation) - Domestic usurpation of governmental authority is simply conquest writ small. If the usurper try to also change the form of government, we can add tyranny to his crimes. This is because, in consenting to the government, implicit in that consent is the people's right to determine which members of society will wield the power they have ceded. Any actions taken by a usurper do not have the force of law, until that time as the usurper actually wins the consent of the people.
------------------------
How does this discussion of the laws of conquest inform the Israel-Palestine situation? Is Israel's occupation of the West Bank unlawful because the new generation of Palestinians has the right to self-determined government? Or are they still acting against the previous generation of aggressors? How does the continued strife, if perpetuated by the rising generation, affect Israel's obligations to them?
Sudden question: Was Woodrow Wilson' wife a usurper? Was Elanor Roosevelt? Or do these circumstances fall under the "prerogative" exception retained by the executive? (But how does a non-executive invoke prerogative power?)
But in the case of a nation that wins a war lawfully against an aggressor, what are the obligations? The conquerer gains no more authority over his own people than before-- no aggrandizement allowed. Over the conquered people, he has no authority if they did not participate nor acquiesce in the aggression-- an illegal war perpetrated by leaders can't be assumed to be through the consent of the people. It is true that the conquerer has a right to property to repair the injustice done to him. But this right does not extend to depriving women and children of the property they inherit from their-- even their wicked-- husbands and fathers. In these cases the men never had the power to risk their wives' and children's property to begin with, so it cannot be forfeited.
The conquerer does not have the right to impose a new system of government without the consent of the people, either. It is true that they must impose some restrictions, to ensure justice for their own injury. But this imposition has no force on the children in that nation, who retain the natural right to establish, through their own consent, their own system of government upon coming of age. To prevent this is its own injustice.
XVII (Of Usurpation) - Domestic usurpation of governmental authority is simply conquest writ small. If the usurper try to also change the form of government, we can add tyranny to his crimes. This is because, in consenting to the government, implicit in that consent is the people's right to determine which members of society will wield the power they have ceded. Any actions taken by a usurper do not have the force of law, until that time as the usurper actually wins the consent of the people.
------------------------
How does this discussion of the laws of conquest inform the Israel-Palestine situation? Is Israel's occupation of the West Bank unlawful because the new generation of Palestinians has the right to self-determined government? Or are they still acting against the previous generation of aggressors? How does the continued strife, if perpetuated by the rising generation, affect Israel's obligations to them?
Sudden question: Was Woodrow Wilson' wife a usurper? Was Elanor Roosevelt? Or do these circumstances fall under the "prerogative" exception retained by the executive? (But how does a non-executive invoke prerogative power?)
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, XIII - XV
XIII (Of the Subordination of the Powers of the Commonwealth) - The legislature has the highest power in the commonwealth. But if it happens that they abuse their power, the people have the right to dissolve the government, for the people retain supreme power at all times.
The executive is in all ways subordinate to the legislature (excepting those cases where the executive has a hand in crafting legislation), for he can do nothing but what the laws of the legislature direct. The executive does have the power, however, to administer and direct the selections of new legislative bodies from time to time, or on a fixed schedule. In this role he is acting directly as a representative of the people, who naturally retain this power.
It is important to make sure the makeup of the legislature is flexible enough to adapt to changing popluations and demographics.
XIV (Of Prerogative) - At times, it is necessary for the executive to invent law on the fly, or even to violate the laws on the books, with a mind to preserving the fundamental Natural law. There is nothing illegitimate about this, for it is possible and even likely that the legitimate written laws will, in certain unforeseen circumstances, lead to a greater harm to the community. In fact, early governments probably operated under these circumstances most of the time.
As a protection against abuse, however, the legislature always has a power to check, through new laws, the decisions the executive has made through his prerogative. Also, the people retain the right to check the executive's overreach.
The biggest danger for abuse is when a subsequent executive uses the previous executive's prerogative as a model for overall governance. The whole point of prerogative is that it is not a rule-- it is invoked only to address immediate circumstance.
There is no body that can rightly and purely decide between the legislature and executive in these cases. Life goes on. What recourse do the citizens ultimately have against what they perceive as an abuse of prerogative? All the aforementioned procedures and checks. But in the meantime, pray. [Seriously.]
XV (Of Paternal, Political and Despotical Power, Considered Together) - Recap.
-------------------------
Locke is suggesting that the rules of good government are not nearly as fixed as some would hope them to be. Real governing occurs in the gaps between the established rules, and depends on the wisdom and rational judgment of all the actors and participants involved. And so his vision of government depends on trusting that every man is rational, and could at all times fend for himself, only choosing not to out of a perceived benefit of ceding that power. It's very optimistic.
The executive is in all ways subordinate to the legislature (excepting those cases where the executive has a hand in crafting legislation), for he can do nothing but what the laws of the legislature direct. The executive does have the power, however, to administer and direct the selections of new legislative bodies from time to time, or on a fixed schedule. In this role he is acting directly as a representative of the people, who naturally retain this power.
It is important to make sure the makeup of the legislature is flexible enough to adapt to changing popluations and demographics.
XIV (Of Prerogative) - At times, it is necessary for the executive to invent law on the fly, or even to violate the laws on the books, with a mind to preserving the fundamental Natural law. There is nothing illegitimate about this, for it is possible and even likely that the legitimate written laws will, in certain unforeseen circumstances, lead to a greater harm to the community. In fact, early governments probably operated under these circumstances most of the time.
As a protection against abuse, however, the legislature always has a power to check, through new laws, the decisions the executive has made through his prerogative. Also, the people retain the right to check the executive's overreach.
The biggest danger for abuse is when a subsequent executive uses the previous executive's prerogative as a model for overall governance. The whole point of prerogative is that it is not a rule-- it is invoked only to address immediate circumstance.
There is no body that can rightly and purely decide between the legislature and executive in these cases. Life goes on. What recourse do the citizens ultimately have against what they perceive as an abuse of prerogative? All the aforementioned procedures and checks. But in the meantime, pray. [Seriously.]
XV (Of Paternal, Political and Despotical Power, Considered Together) - Recap.
-------------------------
Locke is suggesting that the rules of good government are not nearly as fixed as some would hope them to be. Real governing occurs in the gaps between the established rules, and depends on the wisdom and rational judgment of all the actors and participants involved. And so his vision of government depends on trusting that every man is rational, and could at all times fend for himself, only choosing not to out of a perceived benefit of ceding that power. It's very optimistic.
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, X - XII
X (Of the Forms of a Commonwealth) - The community can choose to design a pure democracy, an oligarchy, a hereditary or elective monarchy, or mix and match these pieces at will. The most important element in the design of a commonwealth is the form of the legislature, which ultimately gives the commonwealth its character.
XI (Of the Extent of the Legislative Power) - The power of the legislature is not unlimited. Indeed, it has precisely those limits that each man in the state of nature was limited to unto himself. That man had no authority to compel the life or property of any other. Nor does the legislature have the authority to seize the property of any citizen without his due consent. (Otherwise, how could a legislature of such power have earned the consent of that citizen to begin with?)
The laws emanating from the legislature must be written and clear, never arbitrary.
How important is this limitation? Even in the case where a superior military officer does have the authority to risk the life of his subordinate, he does not have the authority to compel his subordinate's money or other property. So there.
To that end, it is better to design a legislature so as to prevent long-serving members from thinking themselves as having the power over the estates of the remainder of the citizenry. This is especially a danger when that legislator believes himself to doing so for the improved good of the community-- in fact, this is the ultimate danger of any commonwealth. It is always illegitimate, for it directly deprives the citizens of the nature rights they would have possessed under the state of nature, which are inalienable, no matter the good intent.
Of course, it is necessary for there to be a power of taxation. But it must always occur through the consent of the taxed. Period.
It is also illegitimate for the legislators to cede any ounce of legislative power to any other person or body-- for this is not the original agreement of the members of society, and deprives them of their original rights.
XII (The Legislative, Executive, and Federative Power of the Commonwealth) - The legislature need not continually meet-- in fact, it's better if it doesn't. It only needs to quickly write the law, then return to live among the citizenry under that same law. Therefore, it is important that the same body not actually administer the law. Instead, the continually operating part of the government is the executive.
A third function of government is the regulation of affairs with other societies-- called the "federative" powers. The state of affairs between separate commonwealths is not unlike the state of nature between individual men. Accordingly, these affairs cannot always be administered under previously established rules; more flexibility is required, often instant flexibility. In practice, it is very likely that the federative powers will be wielded by the same exective as administers domestic affairs.
-------------------------
OK, but what kind of consent is needed for the legislature to legitimately take the property of the citizens through taxation? The process ought to be spelled out in as much detail as is feasible-- probably nothing else in the design of government is as important.
XI (Of the Extent of the Legislative Power) - The power of the legislature is not unlimited. Indeed, it has precisely those limits that each man in the state of nature was limited to unto himself. That man had no authority to compel the life or property of any other. Nor does the legislature have the authority to seize the property of any citizen without his due consent. (Otherwise, how could a legislature of such power have earned the consent of that citizen to begin with?)
The laws emanating from the legislature must be written and clear, never arbitrary.
How important is this limitation? Even in the case where a superior military officer does have the authority to risk the life of his subordinate, he does not have the authority to compel his subordinate's money or other property. So there.
To that end, it is better to design a legislature so as to prevent long-serving members from thinking themselves as having the power over the estates of the remainder of the citizenry. This is especially a danger when that legislator believes himself to doing so for the improved good of the community-- in fact, this is the ultimate danger of any commonwealth. It is always illegitimate, for it directly deprives the citizens of the nature rights they would have possessed under the state of nature, which are inalienable, no matter the good intent.
Of course, it is necessary for there to be a power of taxation. But it must always occur through the consent of the taxed. Period.
It is also illegitimate for the legislators to cede any ounce of legislative power to any other person or body-- for this is not the original agreement of the members of society, and deprives them of their original rights.
XII (The Legislative, Executive, and Federative Power of the Commonwealth) - The legislature need not continually meet-- in fact, it's better if it doesn't. It only needs to quickly write the law, then return to live among the citizenry under that same law. Therefore, it is important that the same body not actually administer the law. Instead, the continually operating part of the government is the executive.
A third function of government is the regulation of affairs with other societies-- called the "federative" powers. The state of affairs between separate commonwealths is not unlike the state of nature between individual men. Accordingly, these affairs cannot always be administered under previously established rules; more flexibility is required, often instant flexibility. In practice, it is very likely that the federative powers will be wielded by the same exective as administers domestic affairs.
-------------------------
OK, but what kind of consent is needed for the legislature to legitimately take the property of the citizens through taxation? The process ought to be spelled out in as much detail as is feasible-- probably nothing else in the design of government is as important.
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, VIII - IX
VIII (Of the Beginning of Political Societies) - So once men come together, giving up the autonomy they enjoy in the state of nature, the society must function as a whole. The only way this works is for all to aquiesce to the decisions of the majority-- resistance on the part of any minority means they are asserting their own decisions in the place of the whole, which by definition is the breakdown of the society. This instability cannot possibly last for long.
Objections. First, it might be said that we have no evidence for men coming together, mutually agreeing to cede authority to the group. Is this all simply myth or fantasy? Answer: it's not surprising that early societies have no records of this action, but it simply must have taken place. Most of our societies are so long-lasting that the moment of origin is long in the past. And in fact, we do have evidence of just these kinds of decisions-- breakaway groups that strike out on their own.
Next: But these societies commonly are ruled by a monarch. Doesn't this work against your argument? Answer: Not at all. It's entirely plausible that early societies would grant final authority in an individual deemed wise. It's entirely unsurprising that they would allow authority to carry through the wise family-- everything's easier that way. What we do see, though, is interruption of the hereditary line when things get beyond the patience of the society-- exactly what I've been saying. Improvements to the design of the system can come incrementally. When they do, they come through the consent of the majority.
Finally: But what actually happens is men grow up in a society, and feel bound to that society, right? Where's the moment of rational consent? Answer: Not surprising that most stay in the society with which they are familiar. That society often confers many advantages that a man would not want to forego. But always, the decision to stay is an act of will; the society has no power to compel participation and residence. The society only has authority over those who grant it authority; a return to the state of nature is always an option, and is often taken, to no penalty from the society that is left behind.
IX (Of the Ends of Political Society and Government) - So why would a man give up the state of nature for a more restricted life? In a word, security. First, security in his private property; second, security in neutral and impartial judgment; third, security that the execution of justice will actually be completed.
Man possesses two great powers in the state of nature. The first is the right to set his own course of action in all things. The second is to exact valid force over those who interfere with his liberty. The first he cedes to the legislature in a society; the second he cedes to the executive.
------------------------
Not much documentation of the creation of a new civil society, eh? Wait a hundred years or so, John.
Key note: Locke repeatedly refers to the fundamental rights of man as life, liberty and property. Ultimately, this means that econonomic freedom is of the same importance as political freedom. How did the New Deal Supreme Court screw that up so badly? To be continued...
Objections. First, it might be said that we have no evidence for men coming together, mutually agreeing to cede authority to the group. Is this all simply myth or fantasy? Answer: it's not surprising that early societies have no records of this action, but it simply must have taken place. Most of our societies are so long-lasting that the moment of origin is long in the past. And in fact, we do have evidence of just these kinds of decisions-- breakaway groups that strike out on their own.
Next: But these societies commonly are ruled by a monarch. Doesn't this work against your argument? Answer: Not at all. It's entirely plausible that early societies would grant final authority in an individual deemed wise. It's entirely unsurprising that they would allow authority to carry through the wise family-- everything's easier that way. What we do see, though, is interruption of the hereditary line when things get beyond the patience of the society-- exactly what I've been saying. Improvements to the design of the system can come incrementally. When they do, they come through the consent of the majority.
Finally: But what actually happens is men grow up in a society, and feel bound to that society, right? Where's the moment of rational consent? Answer: Not surprising that most stay in the society with which they are familiar. That society often confers many advantages that a man would not want to forego. But always, the decision to stay is an act of will; the society has no power to compel participation and residence. The society only has authority over those who grant it authority; a return to the state of nature is always an option, and is often taken, to no penalty from the society that is left behind.
IX (Of the Ends of Political Society and Government) - So why would a man give up the state of nature for a more restricted life? In a word, security. First, security in his private property; second, security in neutral and impartial judgment; third, security that the execution of justice will actually be completed.
Man possesses two great powers in the state of nature. The first is the right to set his own course of action in all things. The second is to exact valid force over those who interfere with his liberty. The first he cedes to the legislature in a society; the second he cedes to the executive.
------------------------
Not much documentation of the creation of a new civil society, eh? Wait a hundred years or so, John.
Key note: Locke repeatedly refers to the fundamental rights of man as life, liberty and property. Ultimately, this means that econonomic freedom is of the same importance as political freedom. How did the New Deal Supreme Court screw that up so badly? To be continued...
Sunday, May 08, 2011
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, VI - VII
VI (Of Paternal Power) - It is the duty of parents-- both mother and father-- to raise, care for, and teach their children, who are unable to comport themselves with the civil laws and the law of reason while they have still not reached the age of reason. Until that time, the parents must show what it is to act within the bounds of rules by setting up rules for their children. It is the duty of children, upon reaching adulthood, to continue to honore their parents, but this does not mean they are duty-bound to continue to follow their parents' directives. After grown children are able to live according to their own reason, parents can no longer legitimately exercise that kind of restraint.
The authority parents have over their children is not a model for the authority monarchs could have over their subjects. So don't even go there.
VII (Of Political or Civil Society) - Marriage for life developed in mankind because each child born to a woman arrived before the previous had grown old enough and rational enough to care for himself. Since the duty of the father to each child continued over long stretches of time, it was important that the mother and father of each child be tied to one another for the duration.
Civil, or political, society comes into being when each citizen gives up the right he has within the state of Nature to exact punishment for crimes. When all instead cede this power to a governing authority, the better to avoid poor or extreme application of the law of Nature, those men have established a real society. Note that a monarchy government is incompatible with this definition, for it allows a single man, the monarch, to continue to possess the same powers over life and death that all possessed within the state of Nature. And one more point about that: if other men witness the monarch exercising that right, it is likely they will conclude that the right can be exercised against the monarch as well-- even if only for self-preservation-- and we're right back to the state of Nature anyway.
The authority parents have over their children is not a model for the authority monarchs could have over their subjects. So don't even go there.
VII (Of Political or Civil Society) - Marriage for life developed in mankind because each child born to a woman arrived before the previous had grown old enough and rational enough to care for himself. Since the duty of the father to each child continued over long stretches of time, it was important that the mother and father of each child be tied to one another for the duration.
Civil, or political, society comes into being when each citizen gives up the right he has within the state of Nature to exact punishment for crimes. When all instead cede this power to a governing authority, the better to avoid poor or extreme application of the law of Nature, those men have established a real society. Note that a monarchy government is incompatible with this definition, for it allows a single man, the monarch, to continue to possess the same powers over life and death that all possessed within the state of Nature. And one more point about that: if other men witness the monarch exercising that right, it is likely they will conclude that the right can be exercised against the monarch as well-- even if only for self-preservation-- and we're right back to the state of Nature anyway.
Saturday, May 07, 2011
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, V
V (Of Property) - A right to self-preservation means an automatic right to the things necessary for self-preservation: food and shelter, at least. But where does the concept of "property" come in?
First, we might consider the wild of Nature to be there for public consumption. But if anyone is actually to make use of, say, the fruit of a tree, he necessarily makes use of it to the exclusion of anyone else's use of it. Each man naturally has a property claim also on his own body, and so his own labor. And when his labor adjusts Nature for the purposes of satisfying his needs, he acquires property rights over that portion of Nature to which he applied himself. Simply put, the man who gathers acorns owns the acorns the moment he gathers them-- common law will get us this far (otherwise he would need the consent of everyone else before claiming possession over so simple a thing.)
These property rights are not unlimited, of course. A man has no right to possess that which he will not make use of, and so will subsequently go to waste.
OK, so what about land? Still simple: working the land confers possession. And there is plenty of land for each man to find his own parcel to work. The only exception is that land which has been preserved for public use by the legitimate public authority. "Subdue the earth and have dominion over it" are a cause and effect.
This could probably have worked forever-- there's plenty of land! Hell, just use America if it comes to that. But at some point, this natural development was interrupted by the use of money, to assign the possession of larger pieces of land to fewer people. This is entirely natural, the fruit of man's cleverness. Overall, it's a good thing. At this point, our civilization has developed to the point that 99% of the goods we get from nature are already infused with some kind of human labor to make them happen. Proof: look at how the native Americans live-- surrounded by as much land as they could care to use, but not living well on it. And look: we eat bread, not acorns; we wear silk, not skins. V.43:
We're watching the re-development of all this in America as we speak.
----------------------
I'm having ideological whiplash reading this against 21st century mores. Suck on this, luddites, eco-warriors, and Gaia worshipers.
Locke is clearly working off of a primitive labor theory of value. That's good as far as it goes, but without further development it devolves into a disastrous theory and wasteful make-work programs. But Locke doesn't consider the possibility of non-useful labor at all. In fact, such a thing could only happen after piggy-backing on an established system of money. Man, this stuff gets complicated in a hurry.
Love the quoted paragraph, a precursor to the "I, Pencil" essay I discovered sometime last year.
Locke's perspective of the American continent is fascinating.
First, we might consider the wild of Nature to be there for public consumption. But if anyone is actually to make use of, say, the fruit of a tree, he necessarily makes use of it to the exclusion of anyone else's use of it. Each man naturally has a property claim also on his own body, and so his own labor. And when his labor adjusts Nature for the purposes of satisfying his needs, he acquires property rights over that portion of Nature to which he applied himself. Simply put, the man who gathers acorns owns the acorns the moment he gathers them-- common law will get us this far (otherwise he would need the consent of everyone else before claiming possession over so simple a thing.)
These property rights are not unlimited, of course. A man has no right to possess that which he will not make use of, and so will subsequently go to waste.
OK, so what about land? Still simple: working the land confers possession. And there is plenty of land for each man to find his own parcel to work. The only exception is that land which has been preserved for public use by the legitimate public authority. "Subdue the earth and have dominion over it" are a cause and effect.
This could probably have worked forever-- there's plenty of land! Hell, just use America if it comes to that. But at some point, this natural development was interrupted by the use of money, to assign the possession of larger pieces of land to fewer people. This is entirely natural, the fruit of man's cleverness. Overall, it's a good thing. At this point, our civilization has developed to the point that 99% of the goods we get from nature are already infused with some kind of human labor to make them happen. Proof: look at how the native Americans live-- surrounded by as much land as they could care to use, but not living well on it. And look: we eat bread, not acorns; we wear silk, not skins. V.43:
It is labour, then, which puts the greatest part of value upon land, without which it would scarcely be worth anything; it is to that we owe the greatest part of all its useful products; for all that the straw, bran, bread, of that acre of wheat, is more worth than the product of an acre of as good land which lies wasted is all the effect of labour. For it is not barely the ploughman's pains, the reaper's and thresher's toil, and the baker's sweat, is to be counted into the bread we eat; the labour of those who broke the oxen, who digged and wrought the iron and stones, who felled and framed the timber employed about the plough, mill, oven, or any other utensils, which are a vast number, requisite to this corn, from its sowing to its being made bread, must all be charged on the account of labour, and received as an effect of that; Nature and the earth furnished only the almost worthless materials as in themselves. It would be a strange catalogue of things that industry provided and made use of about every loaf of bread before it came to our use if we could trace them; iron, wood, leather, bark, timber, stone, bricks, coals, lime, cloth, dyeing-drugs, pitch, tar, masts, ropes and all the materials made use of by any of the workmen, to any part of the work, all which it would be almost impossible, at least too long, to reckon up.And the development of money, which made all this industry go, is easy enough to explain. A man who did gather more than he could use before it perished would be wise to trade away his surplus for something of a more permanent enjoyment-- even if that thing be a merely aesthetically appealing rock. Without the possibility of some item or object or material acting as the storage of value, such surplus would never happen-- for it would merely represent wasted effort and labor.
We're watching the re-development of all this in America as we speak.
----------------------
I'm having ideological whiplash reading this against 21st century mores. Suck on this, luddites, eco-warriors, and Gaia worshipers.
Locke is clearly working off of a primitive labor theory of value. That's good as far as it goes, but without further development it devolves into a disastrous theory and wasteful make-work programs. But Locke doesn't consider the possibility of non-useful labor at all. In fact, such a thing could only happen after piggy-backing on an established system of money. Man, this stuff gets complicated in a hurry.
Love the quoted paragraph, a precursor to the "I, Pencil" essay I discovered sometime last year.
Locke's perspective of the American continent is fascinating.
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, III - IV
III (Of the State of War) - When one is in a declared or open state of war with another, that other automatically has, through the natural right of self-preservation, the right to kill the first. It is known that he who is at war with me desires to capture or enslave (literally or otherwise) me. With that knowledge and expectation, I can do nothing else but try to prevent that from happening.
IV (Of Slavery) - Liberty in society consists in the freedom to act within the rules and laws established a legislative system that has the consent of the governed. Liberty is not the ability act according to one's own raw desires.
Man cannot enslave himself to another, for the same reason that he cannot give up his own life. [Because it's contrary to man's drive to self-preservation?] The most that can be done is that a man, legitimately punishable by death for a crime, could instead be enslaved by the injured party. Even in this scenario, the "slave" could despise this state and seek the death he deserves instead. Other situations that approach slavery should be viewed instead as labor compacts-- and the difference is, the "master" does not have absolute power at any time, and couldn't legitimately, say, kill him or otherwise interfere with his natural freedom at all. In fact, doing so would instantly break the compact.
--------------------------
Tons of stuff in here. Right off the bat, there's a response to extreme libertarianism. Freedom really is bounded by legitimate legislative authority. We'll see what the limits of that authority are though-- how do we preserve property rights, and curtail abortion right, through the same civil authority? (One answer: we elect lawmakers who follow through on such a plan. It's a huge problem that the courts interfere with legitimate lawmaking ability. Maybe. Hmm.)
Interesting anwer to advocates of assisted suicide here. According to Locke's view of our fundamental self-preserving nature, we don't have the authority to seek our own deaths. To do so violates our fundamental nature, without which... none of the other individual rights hold up, because there's nothing fundamental within ourselves that we would have to respect in any other. Even the sick owe it to the rest of society not to open that door. (It is not a fundamental part of our nature to be free from pain. But it is, naturally, a part of our nature to try to flee pain. Hmm.)
Completely unexpected discussion of the problems of slavery. From this brief chapter, it seems the violations of justice present in the American system of slavery were: a) the capture of African men and women from their homeland, and b) the claim of slaveowners of absolute power over their "property", which is impossible. The labor itself wasn't inherently an injustice (?). Hmm.
IV (Of Slavery) - Liberty in society consists in the freedom to act within the rules and laws established a legislative system that has the consent of the governed. Liberty is not the ability act according to one's own raw desires.
Man cannot enslave himself to another, for the same reason that he cannot give up his own life. [Because it's contrary to man's drive to self-preservation?] The most that can be done is that a man, legitimately punishable by death for a crime, could instead be enslaved by the injured party. Even in this scenario, the "slave" could despise this state and seek the death he deserves instead. Other situations that approach slavery should be viewed instead as labor compacts-- and the difference is, the "master" does not have absolute power at any time, and couldn't legitimately, say, kill him or otherwise interfere with his natural freedom at all. In fact, doing so would instantly break the compact.
--------------------------
Tons of stuff in here. Right off the bat, there's a response to extreme libertarianism. Freedom really is bounded by legitimate legislative authority. We'll see what the limits of that authority are though-- how do we preserve property rights, and curtail abortion right, through the same civil authority? (One answer: we elect lawmakers who follow through on such a plan. It's a huge problem that the courts interfere with legitimate lawmaking ability. Maybe. Hmm.)
Interesting anwer to advocates of assisted suicide here. According to Locke's view of our fundamental self-preserving nature, we don't have the authority to seek our own deaths. To do so violates our fundamental nature, without which... none of the other individual rights hold up, because there's nothing fundamental within ourselves that we would have to respect in any other. Even the sick owe it to the rest of society not to open that door. (It is not a fundamental part of our nature to be free from pain. But it is, naturally, a part of our nature to try to flee pain. Hmm.)
Completely unexpected discussion of the problems of slavery. From this brief chapter, it seems the violations of justice present in the American system of slavery were: a) the capture of African men and women from their homeland, and b) the claim of slaveowners of absolute power over their "property", which is impossible. The labor itself wasn't inherently an injustice (?). Hmm.
Second Treatise Of Civil Government, I - II
I - Even if the hereditary divine right of kings was initially established by God and imbued into Adam, in the intervening years we have lost complete grasp of how that line of succession should be followed. Hence, we must answer this question anyway: What does it mean for a figure to have authority over another, in many different contexts. In the specific case of political authority, it consists in the right to make laws, mete out punishment (up to and including lawful death), defending the population from foreign injury, and all done with an eye to the public good.
II (Of the State of Nature) - First, recognize that we possess freedom within the bounds of the Laws of Nature. Second, within that Law is each man's direction to self-preservation and thriving. Third, for the aforementioned reasons, men born into the same community are at the same station in life-- that of subordination to their Maker. Given all that, every man has the right to execute punishment on another who interferes with or disrupts his own Natural rights. II.6:
Contraposed to this universal right, there is also the individual right of the aggrieved to extract satisfaction from the wrongdoer or injurer. Some will say this is going too far, that placing this power within the individual opens the door to exaggeration of injury and improper punishment. Keep in mind we're discussing justice in the state of Nature-- of course in a mature government it would be good to move this power into formal courts and within the people at large. But then, how is that an argument for investing supreme power in a single individual monarch? If we are to design safeguards for the meting out of justice, we'd better do so more carefully than that.
--------------------------
Looks like the origin of what we call human rights really does depend upon human nature as infused in us by God, our Creator. And not entirely because every aspect of those rights is individually programmed into every human being-- that would be quite a trick to try to prove, working out the mechanics of God's creation of Man. Instead, Locke's point can be boiled down to a much simpler argument: it is our subordination under God that puts us all at essentially the same moral level, and it is from that perspective that we have the responsibility to ensure that no one can interfere with at least the basics of another's nature. It is only if we are not all born into an identical station under God that it would be possible that some are born to a higher station, and can claim for themselves authority and power over the others. Nietzche's Superman?
Don't forget though, at the moment, we're only talking about Man actually living in an undeveloped state of Nature. The consequences of all this may change as society is built.
II (Of the State of Nature) - First, recognize that we possess freedom within the bounds of the Laws of Nature. Second, within that Law is each man's direction to self-preservation and thriving. Third, for the aforementioned reasons, men born into the same community are at the same station in life-- that of subordination to their Maker. Given all that, every man has the right to execute punishment on another who interferes with or disrupts his own Natural rights. II.6:
Every one as he is bound to preserve himself, and not to quit his station wilfully, so by the like reason, when his own preservation comes not in competition, ought he as much as he can to preserve the rest of mankind, and not unless it be to do justice on an offender, take away or impair the life, or what tends to the preservation of the life, the liberty, health, limb, or goods of another.Evidence for this: otherwise, by what right can a nation such as ours execute punishment upon a foreigner-- who, having not participated in the legislation of law, is not bound to live under it?
Contraposed to this universal right, there is also the individual right of the aggrieved to extract satisfaction from the wrongdoer or injurer. Some will say this is going too far, that placing this power within the individual opens the door to exaggeration of injury and improper punishment. Keep in mind we're discussing justice in the state of Nature-- of course in a mature government it would be good to move this power into formal courts and within the people at large. But then, how is that an argument for investing supreme power in a single individual monarch? If we are to design safeguards for the meting out of justice, we'd better do so more carefully than that.
--------------------------
Looks like the origin of what we call human rights really does depend upon human nature as infused in us by God, our Creator. And not entirely because every aspect of those rights is individually programmed into every human being-- that would be quite a trick to try to prove, working out the mechanics of God's creation of Man. Instead, Locke's point can be boiled down to a much simpler argument: it is our subordination under God that puts us all at essentially the same moral level, and it is from that perspective that we have the responsibility to ensure that no one can interfere with at least the basics of another's nature. It is only if we are not all born into an identical station under God that it would be possible that some are born to a higher station, and can claim for themselves authority and power over the others. Nietzche's Superman?
Don't forget though, at the moment, we're only talking about Man actually living in an undeveloped state of Nature. The consequences of all this may change as society is built.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)